Diderot expressed a conviction that during a performance, the actors must retain his or her distinct self independent of the role. According to Diderot, being able to refrain being subject of a role’s emotions helped an actor to act those emotions (represent) to the audience in the particular way he or she determines most effective. Experiencing a distinction between the self and the role as far as emotions are concerned whilst on-stage is what Diderot described as the psychological duality of the actor's 'paradox' (Diderot, 1773-78).
Contradicting Theories Constantin Sergeyevich Stanislavsky was born in Moscow in 1863. His contributions to the process of acting are perhaps the single greatest contribution anyone made in the 20th Century. As a renown actor and director, Stanislavsky always emphasised that the theatre only acquired meaning if it moved beyond a mere external representation acting had always been (Tait, 2002). In his time in theatre, Stanislavsky created a dynamic approach to the emotional and psychological aspects of theatrical acting.
The system later to be known as the Stanislavsky method/system placed the expression of a role’s emotions as the actor’s main responsibility. An actor has to be believed and felt rather than understood or recognized. Standing in opposition to Diderot’s assertion that acting was an art of representation where the actor had to simulate rather than experience the emotions of a role, Stanislavsky postulated a method acting in which acting became the art of experiencing/presentation the role realistically (Counsell, 1996).
The representation role as postulated by Diderot is thus in complete contrast with the experience role as postulated by Stanislavsky. Diderot asserts that an actor does not live a role rather he or she plays it. As such, the actor must remain cold towards the emotions depicted by the role. What the actor has to do is to act out the emotions with perfection such that the audience sees him or her experiencing while all the actors is doing is representing passively (Bruder, 1986). Therefore, instead of experience the content of his or her act, the actor just accurately represents the content with an artistic finish.
According to Stanislavski however, during the performance, an actor must necessarily live the role every minute when he or she is playing it and every other time after that. Acting thus becomes a series of living and reliving a role with each act recreating the experience anew, living the emotions afresh and reincarnating the emotions always during the moments on stage. Stanislavsky’s approach has a high degree of improvisation in which actors retain the ability to perform the emotions they are experiencing alike to the character of their role (Tait, 2002).
Interiority versus Externality The Diderot school of thought where the actor must remain cold towards the emotions depicted by the role is in support of the concept of externality. Emotions are not felt but represented. What the actor produces on stage is in total contrast of whether he or she feels, it is just an exterior depiction of emotions as required by the role (Carnicke, 1998). Externality theorists and actors have always stressed on the separation of the self and the character as the only way an actor can expertly depict precise emotions whilst on stage.
On the other hand, Stanislavsky’s school of thought urging that the actor must necessarily experience/present the role lies in the interiority realms. In this school of thought the emotions an actor depicts on stage are better expressed if they come from within, as ‘experiences’ or ‘presentation’ rather than ‘acts’. Subscribers to this theory usually advice actors to submerge themselves to the characters, to feel what the character feels, to see things from the character’s point of view, to live the life of the character and show what the character shows.
The border between the self and the character is merged into the third being that audience sees on stage, a being of emotions Stanislavsky called aristol-rol (Carnicke, 2000).
Read More