It is a bit like saying light is darkness or absence is presence. What Sartre means is that freedom is a terrible responsibility if all you have is your one life and nothing more. But this doesn’t make too much sense, if a person believes, like Sartre, that the world is meaningless. The nausea of seeing yourself and your perceptions reflected back in the world or the world filling with yourself is also something to be disagreed with. In a way the kind of existentialism Sartre complains about is really solipsism: the belief that you are the only thing in the world, or the only thing that exists.
If Sartre stopped for a moment to look at the world, he wouldn’t see his own ugly face reflected back in the petal of a flower or in a sunrise: he would see a dazzling display of the natural world and the fact that people are part of it all, that this is designed to be our world where we should be happy. Camus thinks of things a bit differently. The drudgery and meaningless of his current existence plagues Merseault, the main character of his most famous book The Stranger. Although his lack of belief, or exclusive self-belief, inspires the notion that he is free and has the will to choose how he would like to live, instead his life is circumscribed by things beyond his control.
There is always the temptation to desperation, but it is an attitude or perspective that Camus ultimately rejects. He says that the only philosophical question is that of suicide, and using philosophy comes to the conclusion that suicide is not a correct approach to life. This is the message of The Stranger. Merseault, convicted of murder (and of having no emotions), could resign himself to death, even embrace it. Instead, in the strange final words of the book he does not. He sets himself against extinction with a different attitude.
As if that blind rage had washed me clean, rid me of hope; for the first time, in that night alive with signs and stars, I opened myself to the gentle indifference of the world. Finding it so much like myself — so like a brother, really — I felt that I had been happy and that I was happy again. For everything to be consummated, for me to feel less alone, I had only to wish that there be a large crowd of spectators the day of my execution and that they greet me with cries of hate. This is the scorn that Camus talks about in his philosophy.
Knowing his fate and knowing he will be subject to it, no matter what else happens, Merseault does no embrace. Instead, he welcomes the scorn of the crowd and returns it. This is the independence of spirit that makes life worth living, Camus seems to be saying. Camus’ early philosophy is not without its critics. They see the proud scorn of Merseault as overly romantic and too much of an embrace of violence. Merseault is a seductive figure and seems to imply that there is no such thing as guilt.
What is murder, Camus seems to be saying, just something that happens; one cannot be guilty of it as guilt is only constructed by the social machine. The critic English Showalter find the “pose of indifference, the concealed longing for recognition, the devious provocations, all [characterizing] the not-yet successful young writer . . .” that Camus then was before The Stranger’s publication. He believes Camus later set out to correct this novel. By the time he wrote The Fall, Camus recognized the inadequacy of his presentation in The Stranger, in part perhaps because he had outgrown his youthful romanticism.
When he returns to the problem in The Fall, however, it is not only because he wants to correct an earlier mistake but also because the “innocent murderer” still haunts his conscience.4 We can see in his style how Camus reifies his own philosophy. As the years go by and he has made his point, his style too changes. The world of [his] fiction [is] perceived by the reader as through a glass darkly, a glass that, in the case of L’Etranger, Sartre had likened to the glass door of a telephone booth.
Read More