StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

Determinism versus Free Will - Essay Example

Cite this document
Summary
The paper "Determinism versus Free Will" describes that counselors have never had the luxury of waiting for the final resolution of great issues, since they have always been confronted in their work with a more pressing problem - the perceived needs of the client seated before them…
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER97.2% of users find it useful
Determinism versus Free Will
Read Text Preview

Extract of sample "Determinism versus Free Will"

Determinism Versus Free Will Of DETERMINISM VERSUS FREE WILL INTRODUCTION As Einstein's position suggested, onemight profit from challenging the belief that free will and determinism represent polar opposite extremes of a single dimension. Perhaps these two concepts are better understood as being located on two separate dimensions A similar conceptual revision (Constantinople, 1973) sparked an enormous surge of research in the domain of sex-role orientation. If 20 years ago one had complimented a man on his fine feminine characteristics, he might well have been insulted by the compliment. Why Until 2 decades ago, masculinity and femininity were thought to be polar opposites, so highlighting one's feminine characteristics typically meant denying the person's masculine traits. This was not only an accepted conceptual position, it was also a computational fact of life with all of the then-existing sex-role orientation measures. However, Constantinople's (1973) conceptual reorganization allowed for the possibility of two independent dimensions: masculinity and femininity. From this new vantage point, one is not forced to deny one set of characteristics in order to assert possession of high levels of the other. Now, people can be different combinations (conceptually and computationally): high on both masculinity and femininity (androgynous); high on one and low on the other (stereotypically masculine or stereotypically feminine); or low on both dimensions (undifferentiated). It was this simple, conceptual reformulation that appeared to spark the present revolution in sex-role research. DISCUSSION Might a similar reformulation of the free will-determinism question stimulate new solutions to an antinomy that has perplexed thinkers for more than 25 centuries Before sketching a re-conceptualization of the free will versus determinism issue, this article will offer a working scientist's or a counseling practitioner's specification of the issues--not a philosopher's reformulation of this seemingly everlasting controversy. That is, the definition of terms (such as free will, determinism, nonagentic mechanism) is empirically operationalizable and thus (in this form) amenable to empirical scrutiny. However, in so defining these terms, it becomes unclear exactly what the implications of these conceptual moves (and research findings) might be for philosophical debate on the issues of agency, mechanistic determinism, self-determination, and free will. There have been many different construals of free will (van Inwagen, 1983) over the last two and a half millennia. Some of these construals (e.g., free will results from the absence of any physical constraint upon the agent) clearly do not square with the arguments and research summarized herein. Whenever an agent makes a choice (and then acts for the sake of that choice), however, one might see it as a free choice (and act) if indeed the agent might have chosen to do otherwise ceteris paribus (i.e., all other things being equal). The notion of free will entertained herein is seen in Robert Frost's (1951) poem "The Road Not Taken." Two roads diverged in a wood, and I-- I took the one less traveled by, And that has made all the difference. If Frost's (1951) traveller had also been able to choose "the road more [italics added] traveled by" but instead opted for "the road less [italics added] traveled by," one might assert that he or she had made a free choice. But since the time of Heraclitus (with his point that one can never step in the same river twice), philosophers and scientists recognized the virtual impossibility of meeting the demands of the ceteris paribus condition in such cases. Fortunately, new experimental methodologies now allow for the testing of the causal force of free choice in studies that do fully meet the requirements of the ceteris paribus assumption (see Howard & Myers, 1989). Like free will, the meaning of determinism has changed over time. "Determinism" was until the mid-nineteenth century a theory of the will--a denial of human freedom--and some dictionaries give this as a first meaning. Partly as a result of statistical discussion, it assumed during the 1850s and 1860s its modern and more general meaning, by which the future of the world is held to be wholly determined by its present configuration. What then is the working scientist's definition of determinism It is the belief that events (or effects) are produced by some prior events (or causes). For this article's purpose, reasons can also serve as causes. The opposite of determinism, then, would be acausality or indeterminism. That is, things occur randomly, spontaneously, and are sometimes uncaused. Uncertainty (cf. Price & Chissick, 1977) is a distinctly different concept from the "acausality" that is being suggested as the polar opposite of "determinism." From this perspective, one can readily see why Kimble (1984) found that virtually all psychologists are determinists--as acausality represents the enemy of scientific analysis. Thus, the present reformulation does not suggest that psychologists should deny determinism in any way. Rather, it means that a psychologist can be both a free willist and a determinist. Now one can specify a second, independent dimension that is anchored on one end by free will or complete self-determination--this is defined as an agent's ability to act in a domain completely independently of all nonagentic, mechanistic influences. The opposite of free will, then, would be complete mechanistic determination (whether by physiological factors, environmental influences, unconscious motivations, social influences, genetic or predispositions). At this latter extreme, human choice is seen as completely causally impotent or human choice itself is seen as a completely mechanistically determined phenomenon and not the creation of a free agent. Figure 1 outlines this reconceptualization of the old free will-determinism debate. There does not seem to be a serious scholar who advocates complete acausality in the world, as most scientists strongly (if not completely) espouse deterministic belief systems in their roles as professionals. Thus, few scholars would be far from the "determinist" pole of the first dimension. But what of the self-determination versus nonagentic mechanism dimension Scientists in the physical sciences would seem to be severely skewed toward the nonagentic mechanism pole in their professional work. While individuals in the biological sciences might not be as heavily skewed toward the nonagentic mechanism pole, they certainly would not approach belief in complete self-determination. For researchers in the human sciences, however, compelling arguments can be offered for the role of both self-determination and mechanistic determination in human action. And while the mechanist has always been free to offer a deterministic vision of human action that is scientific (simply by denying free will), because of the foregoing reformulation, a proponent of some version of human self-determination (or free will) can now also be deterministic in his or her theory of human action. THE ROLE OF SELF-DETERMINATION IN HUMAN ACTION The present reformulation of the free will-determinism question does not represent the first analysis to show that the ancient problem rests upon conceptual confusions. May (1981), Rogers (1959), and Rychlak (1979) each resolved the paradoxes of freedom and destiny in their own creative ways. Berger (1963) expressed a reasonable version (for the free will advocate) of the accepted wisdom regarding the relationship between free will (freedom) and determinism (science). Berger's characterization of the state of the human sciences was accurate at the time it was penned--there simply was no methodology for unequivocally ascertaining the proportion of human action attributable to self-determination. Until recently there always remained plausible, mechanistic explanations that might have been responsible for what appeared to be self-determined action in research studies. However, newer methodologies (Howard, 1984; Howard & Conway 1987; Howard, DiGangi, & Johnson, 1988; Howard & Myers, 1989; Howard, Youngs, & Siatczynski, 1989; Lazarick, Fishbein, Loiello, & Howard, 1988) now allow for the unequivocal partitioning of variance in human behavior into self-determination on the one hand, and various nonagentic influences on the other. The justification for this claim is complex and methodological in nature. Summaries of the arguments that support the claim are found in all of the articles cited above. Howard and Myers (1989) articulated, however, the justification in elaborate detail, and specifically addressed criticisms of the claims that variance due to self-determination can be experimentally isolated with the effects of all possible nonagentic, mechanistic factors methodologically removed. Science always strives for a deeper, richer understanding of powers (or capacities, or generative mechanisms) that underlie observed experimental relationships. Watkins (1984) noted, "And our supreme demand is that our science will penetrate deeper and deeper until eventually it achieves ultimate explanations of all phenomena" (p. 128). Recall, for example, that since the time of Gregor Mendel, scientists could specify the relationships between certain characteristics of parents and the likelihood that their offspring would exhibit those characteristics. But it was only in the last 30 years that the mechanisms responsible for the transmission of hereditary traits became clearly understood by scientists (cf. Watson, 1970). Similarly, demonstrating that humans can (to some extent) self-determine their actions represents an important experimental demonstration. But these demonstrations do not (in and of themselves) shed light on the particular mechanisms that enable humans to exhibit this remarkable power to self-determine. FROM A SCHIZOID PLURALISM TO A BINOCULAR VISION OF HUMAN ACTION William James's Principles of Psychology (James, 1890) is arguably the most influential book in the history of psychology. Boring (1929) called James the founder of scientific psychology in America, and it has been argued that his other principles (e.g., pragmatism [James, 1907] and pluralism [James, 1908]) represent the basic values that undergird the scientist-practitioner model in psychology (Howard, 1992). Finally, James is psychology's first and perhaps most steadfast advocate for free will. Why the lavish praise of James It is because this writer disagrees with his treatment of the free will-determinism problem, which has led many to a form of schizoid pluralism in the free will-determinism debate. The principle of pluralism helped James see unity within apparent contradiction, and allowed him to understand many of the paradoxes of human experience. It is well known that a good deal of his emotional torment as a young adult centered on his dread of the possible truth of deterministic analyses of human action, whether of a mechanistic or a biologically reductive sort. Like Tolstoy and Dostoevsky, James had a dread of the demon of absolute determinism in human action, and this dread served to goad many of his creative philosophical moves. James eventually solved the free will-determinism problem to his own satisfaction. James's pluralism saved him from the dilemma of determinism. He believed that when viewed from humanistic perspectives (such as philosophy and theology) human freedom was a reality--thus, his famous quote "My first act of free will shall be to believe in free will" (James, 1920, p. 147). However, science and psychology (in James's view) must be deterministic disciplines; when viewed from this (the scientific) conceptual vantage point, humans are not free, but rather are determined. Thus, James's position on free will-determinism was dualistic in that, "Free will is an issue of fact while being beyond the competence of psychological science" (Viney, 1986, p. 555). This is perhaps the point on which there are now grounds for transcending James's views. It is now possible to recognize free will (or self-determination) to be a causally efficacious agency within a world of nonagentic, deterministic influences. Although science can endorse James's final conclusion that free will-determinism is the correct philosophy, it does so for radically different reasons. It is now possible to be a free willist (to recognize the causal efficacy of self-determination) within the deterministic system of science. Thus, free will-determinists exist, but now from a unified perspective, not from James's dual perspective. James felt that science necessitated the assumption of determinism, but that ethics necessitated the contradictory assumption of human freedom. Thus, in James's thinking, a permanent wall was erected that separated scientific disciplines from ethics. This represents no particular problem for explanations in other sciences, as no one would, for example, want to render moral approbation on planet earth for "speeding" through the heavens, nor would one label sodium an "easy element" for choosing to combine with chlorine at too low a combination temperature. The assumption of determinism is important for the sciences of inanimate and/or insentient objects. But the assumption of freedom of choice is not appropriate, and so for the natural sciences there is no need for a metaphysician (la James's definition) to adjudicate findings from plural, incompatible perspectives (i.e., science and ethics). But the situation is quite different in psychology, and hence James's (1893) prophesy that our Galileos and Lavoisiers would be metaphysicians. FREE WILL-DETERMINISM AND THE PRACTICE OF COUNSELING Two images of human psychology compete for our attention. Academic psychologists, particularly those who work in the "experimental" tradition, make the implicit assumption that men, women, and children are high-grade automata, the patterns of whose behavior are thought to obey something very like natural laws .... It is assumed that there are programs which control action and the task of psychology is to discover the "mechanisms" by which they are implemented. Lay folk, clinical psychologists, lawyers, historians and all of those who have to deal in a practical way with human beings tend to think of people as agents struggling to maintain some sort of reasoned order in their lives against a background flux of emotions, inadequate information, and the ever-present tides of social pressures. I shall try to show that the great differences that mark off these ways of thinking about human psychology are not ultimately grounded in a reasoned weighing of the evidence available to any student of human affairs. They turn in the end on unexamined political and moral assumptions .... Although these profoundly different ways of interpreting and explaining human thought and action have their origin in preferred linguistic forms rather than any compelling facts of the matter, they do have profoundly different practical consequences. They carry with them very distinctive stances as to the moral, political and clinical problems with which modern people are beset. (p. 4) CONCLUSION Counselors have never had the luxury of waiting for the final resolution of great issues (such as the free will-determinism problem), since they have always been confronted in their work with a more pressing problem--the perceived needs of the client seated before them. James was one of the first to see knowledge as activity, not as a product of contemplation. For the counselor, "theories become instruments, not answers to enigmas in which we can rest. We don't lie back upon them, we move forward, and on occasion make nature over [italics added] again by their aid" (James, 1920, p. 380). Counselors employ what James called funded knowledge. That is, knowledge whose chief claim to truth lies in the fact that it is useful and functional. "Funded" means it is based upon both common sense and scientific inquiries. Practitioners are often experts in the psychological phenomenon called coping and coping blends elements of knowledge, action, and hope together. These topics are addressed in Pragmatism (James, 1907). If there is a truth or reality about human nature, James claimed one will not come to know it solely through detached, dispassionate armchair philosophy or laboratory experiments. Counselors will gain insights into human nature by studying acts of self-creation, that is, by accompanying clients as they struggle with the important tasks of devising ways of (in James's felicitous phrase) being good at being human. Now if that is what counselors do in their work, then their philosophy is (as James suggested) Pragmatism--whether or not they know it or acknowledge it. REFERENCES Bandura, A. (1986). Social foundations of thought and action: A social cognitive theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Berger, P. L. (1963). Invitation to sociology: A humanistic perspective. New York: Doubleday. Beutler, L. E. (1983). Eclectic psychotherapy: A systematic approach. New York: Pergamon. Boring, E.G. (1929). A history of experimental psychology. New York: Century. Brammer, L. M., & Shostrom, E. L. (1977). Therapeutic psychology (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Bruner, J. (1986). Actual minds, possible worlds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Cohen, J. (1977). Statistical power analysis for the behavioral sciences. San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Constantinople, A. P. (1973). Masculinity--femininity: An exception to a famous dictum Psychological Bulletin, 80, 389-407. Ford, D. H. (1987). Humans as self-constructing living systems: A developmental perspective on personality and behavior. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Frankl, V. E. (1963). Man's search for meaning (rev. ed.). New York: Washington Square Press. Frost, R. (1951). The road not taken. New York: Holt. Gergen, K. J. (1982). Toward transformation in social knowledge. New York: Springer-Verlag. Harre, R. (1983). Personal being: A theory for individual psychology. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Harre, R. (1974). Blueprint for a new science. In A. Nigel (Ed.), Reconstructing social psychology (pp. 2-25). Totowa, NJ: Littlefield, Adams. Holton, G. (1973). Thematic origins of scientific thought: Kepler to Einstein. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Howard, G. S. (1984). A modest proposal for a revision of strategies in counseling research. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 31,430-442. Howard, G. S. (1985). The role of values in the science of psychology. American Psychologist, 40, 255-265. Howard, G. S. (1989). A tale of two stories: Excursions into a narrative approach to psychology. Notre Dame, IN: Academic Publications. Howard, G. S. (1991). Cuture tales: A narrative approach to thinking, cross-cultural psychology and psychotherapy. American Psychologist, 46, 187-197. Howard, G. S. (1993). Why William James is not recognized as the founder of the scientist-practitioner model. The Counseling Psychologist, 21,118-135. Howard, G. S., & Conway, C. G. (1987). Can there be an empirical science of volitional action American Psychologist, 42, 1034-1036. Howard, G. S., Curtin, T. D., & Johnson, A. J. (1991). Studies of the role of meaning in self-determined action: Point estimation techniques in psychological research: The role of meaning in self-determined action. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 38, 219-226. Howard, G. S., DiGangi, M. L., & Johnson, A. (1988). Life, science, and the role of therapy in the pursuit of happiness. Professional Psychology: Research and Practice, 19, 191-198. Howard, G. S., & Myers, P. (1989). Some experimental investigations of volition. In W. A. Hershberger (Ed.), Volitional action (pp. 335-352). Amsterdam: North-Holland. Howard, G. S., Nance, D. W., & Myers, P. (1987). Adaptive counseling and therapy: A systematic approach to selecting eclectic treatments. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Howard, G. S., Youngs, W. H., & Siatczynski, A.M. (1989). Reforming methodology in psychological research. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 10, 393-412. James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. New York: Holt. James, W. (1893). Psychology: A briefer course. New York: Holt. James, W. (1907/1946). Pragmatism. New York: Longmans, Green, & Co. James, W. (1908/1977). A pluralistic universe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. James, W. (1920). The letters of William James (2 vols.). Boston: Atlantic Monthly Press. Kelly, H. H. (1971). Causal schemata and the attribution process. Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press. Kimble, G. A. (1984). Psychology's two cultures. American Psychologist, 39, 833-839. Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The essential tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lazarick, D. L., Fishbein, S.S., Loiello, M. J., & Howard, G. S. (1988). Practical investigations of volition. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 35, 15-26. Lazarus, A. A. (1971). Behavior therapy and beyond. New York: McGraw-Hill. Lazarus, A. A. (1976). Multimodal behavior therapy. New York: Springer. Lazarus, A. A. (1981). The practice of multimodal therapy. New York: McGraw-Hill. Mahoney, M. J. (1991). Human change processes. New York: Basic Books. Mair, M. (1988). Psychology as story telling. International Journal of Personal Construct Psychology, 1,125-137. Marcus, H., & Nurius, P. (1986). Possible selves. American Psychologist, 41,954-969. May, P. R. A. (1971). Psychotherapy and ataraxic drugs. In A. E. Birgin & S. L. Garfield (Eds.), Handbook of psychotherapy and behavior change (pp. 495-540). New York: Wiley. May, R. (1981). Freedom and destiny. New York: Norton. McAdams, D. P. (1985). Power, intimacy, and the life-story: Personological inquiries in identity. Homewood, IL: Dorsey. McMullin, E. (1983). Values in science. In P. D. Asquith & T. Nickles (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1982 Philosophy of Science Association (Vol. 2, pp. 2-23). East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association. Norcross, J. C. (Ed.). (1986). Handbook of eclectic therapy. New York: Brunner/Mazel. Polkinghorne, D. (1983). Methodology for the human sciences. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Polkinghorne, D. (1988). Narrative knowing and the human sciences. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Porter, T. M. (1986). The rise of statistical thinking 1820-1900. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Price, W., & Chissick, S. (1977). Uncertainty principle and the foundations of quantum mechanics: A fifty year survey. New York: Wiley. @13 = Rogers, C. R. (1959). A theory of therapy, personality, and interpersonal relationships, as developed in the client-centered framework. In S. Koch (Ed.), Psychology: The study of a science (Vol. 3, pp. 184-256). New York: McGraw-Hill. Rychlak, J. (1979). Discovering free will and personal responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press. Rychlak, J. F. (1988). The psychology of rigorous humanism (2nd ed.). New York: New York University Press. Sarbin, T. R. (1986). Narrative psychology. New York: Praeger. Secord, P. F. (1984). Determinism, free will, and self-intervention: A psychological perspective. New Ideas in Psychology, 2, 25-33. Thorne, F. C. (1967). Integrative psychology. Brandon, VT: Clinical Psychology Publishing Co. Toulmin, S. (1981). Concluding comments. In R. A. Kasschau & C. N. Cofer (Eds.), Houston symposium II: Enduring issues in psychology's second century (pp. 211-298). New York: Praeger. van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Oxford: Charendon Press. Viney, D. W. (1986). William James on free will and determinism. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 7, 555-566. Watkins, J. (1984). Science and skepticism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Watson, J. D. (1970). Molecular biology of the gene (2nd ed.). New York: W. A. Benjamin. Wolpe, J. (1958). Psychotherapy by reciprocal inhibition. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. APPENDIX Determinists Nondeterminists All actions result from some Things are uncaused; they just cause(s). happen randomly, spontaneously. Free Willists Mechanists Belief in self-determination and Our actions are the result of agency. People are the cause of mechanisms (e.g., environmental, their own actions. physiological, genetic, cultural) which are completely coercive. FIGURE 1 Free Will-Determinism Dichotomy in Independent Bipolar Dimensions Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(“Determinism verus Free Will Essay Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 2250 words”, n.d.)
Retrieved from https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1524388-determinism-verus-free-will
(Determinism Verus Free Will Essay Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 2250 Words)
https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1524388-determinism-verus-free-will.
“Determinism Verus Free Will Essay Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 2250 Words”, n.d. https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1524388-determinism-verus-free-will.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF Determinism versus Free Will

Determinism, Compatiblism, and Libertarianism

(Name of of Instructor) The Problem of free will Suppose that I can predict the future, down to every detail of what ought to happen.... This paper aims to discuss three positions with regards to the problem of free will.... And part three will discuss the compatibilist view on free will.... For instance, if I can explain my actions through the laws of nature then we have no use for free will anymore.... What does this imply about human beings being free?...
5 Pages (1250 words) Research Paper

Do you have free will or are you determined

The problem of the paper is the question of metaphysics: namely, whether or not people have a free will.... While d'Holbach represents a determinism-only view, Stace offers a view compatible with a free will, and this compatibilist thesis is more correct.... Stace, is the view that free will and determinism are compatible without being logically inconsistent.... This allows claims about individual autonomy in actions to make sense, whereas under the incompatabilism approach, it is logically inconsistent to speak of the coexistence of free will with determinism....
4 Pages (1000 words) Essay

Determinism, Compatibilism, and Libertarianism

Discussion whether human action is pre-determined or is as a result of free will started ancient time and until today no concrete solution has been obtained.... free will, choice, liberty, and determination are terms that seem similar yet different in philosophical meaning.... free will can be termed as spiritual canon.... Absence of causes, conditions is what causes free will.... Time and again free will is interpreted to mean could have done otherwise....
7 Pages (1750 words) Essay

Psychological Issues of Free Will

The essay "Psychological Issues of free will" focuses on the critical analysis of the major psychological issues of free will.... Believing in free will enables us to distinguish between rights and wrong naturally and psychology in the light of various perspectives and theories.... This notion agrees that psychology is responsible for alleviating the grounds of free will.... This notion negates that psychology has a hand in eroding the grounds for believing in free will....
7 Pages (1750 words) Essay

Difference of Free Will and Determinism

The paper "Difference of free will and Determinism" describes that ontologically secure people have a positive sense of their own identity and their place within society.... Existentialists emphasize the role of free will and the choices that are available to an individual.... free will states that we do not feel forced to act.... If determinism were true, no person would be able to change his actions, therefore no one could ever be held morally responsible for his actions....
10 Pages (2500 words) Essay

Free will vs Determinism

Conclusion This evaluation paper has highlighted determinism versus free-will, and assessed whether fate or free will played a more significant part in the main characters meeting with their disastrous destinies.... (Knox 133), depicts the theme of free will against determinism or fate.... Thesis Statement: The purpose of this evaluation paper is to assess whether determinism or free will played the predominant role in the lives of the main characters in the play, who forcefully used their free will in and Number of the Teacher's Evaluation Paper free will VERSUS DETERMINISM IN OEDIPUS THE KING BY SOPHOCLES Introduction The ancient Greek tragedy Oedipus the King by Sophocles first performed in c....
2 Pages (500 words) Essay

Exercise assignments

Discuss whether you believe human beings are free or determined.... If they are free, to what extent are they free?... As Sartre brings up in incredible subtle element, anguish, as the awareness of opportunity, is not something that people welcome; rather, we look for strength, character, and embrace the dialect of flexibility just when it suits us: those demonstrations are recognized by me to be my free demonstrations which precisely match the self I need others to take me to be....
2 Pages (500 words) Coursework

Free Will and Its Critical Concepts in Philosophy

This paper "free will and Its Critical Concepts in Philosophy" focuses on the fact that the debate on the topic of free will is lengthy but interesting.... free will basically questions do men as rational beings have control over their actions and decisions?... Thirdly, free will in scientific terms means the body actions of the body, including mind and brain do not have only physical causes (Fischer, 2005).... Here defining the basic terms used in the context of free will would be helpful: It is the view that all current & future events are regulated by past events coupled with the laws of nature....
8 Pages (2000 words) Assignment
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us