Hence the issue of ‘ethical relativism’ which states that the morality of an action is qualified according to the practices of one’s culture. The crux of the ethical relativists’ belief is that there are no absolutes. This implies that a universal structure to resolve ethical dilemmas across cultures is impossible (Velasquez et.al. 1992). Essentially, in his speech, while he acknowledges the diversity of cultures and the differing beliefs that they hold, Spigelman asserts that this does not mean that there can be compromise in the curbing of gender violence.
In essence, he states that there must be a common ground on which to meet. Ethical relativism focuses on cultures and communities and it is from these that it gets its frame of reference. This contrasts sharply with libertarianism which sees the individual as the standard unit of society. It holds that only the individual has the right to make choices and be accountable for their own deeds. Emphasis is on the dignity of person with its attendant rights and responsibilities. This dignity has been extended to many cultures and is one of the libertarian victories of Western culture.
According to the libertarian creed, the right to security, liberty and property is inherent and not subject to governmental or societal approval; (Boaz, 1998). This view gels well with James Spigelman’s view as outlined in his speech, however, since it is not shared by some of the people whose inherent rights he seeks to protect, who hold family or culture as more important than the individual; then the golden rule again applies here. As Spigelman would prefer that his views be respected there is need to respect the views of others.
A compromise position between these two ethical views is utilitarianism. This is a consequentialist theory which holds that deeds done are correct to the extent that they serve the greatest good for the largest number. The point of this theory is teleological and was first advanced in modern times by John Stuart Mill (1806-1873). The dilemma comes in when defining the ‘greatest good’. Mill’s definition was in terms of a well-being (Aristotle’s eudaimonia) that was differentiated both quantitatively and qualitatively between assorted types of pleasure.
The point is to reduce the ethical question to one of cost to benefit examination and thus reduce the impasse between experiential evidence and normative conclusion(Kay, 1997). To extrapolate this in the Spigelman situation, if utilitarianism was used, it would behove the law to act in a way that resulted in the greatest good being done to the greatest number of people. This could justify the implementation of universal human rights and ban of certain evils, gender violence, for instance. This however, assumes that this is to the benefit of the greater number as stated.
The application of the Golden Rule with regard to all three theories is a very subjective matter; as all three theories can seem to agree on just one thing; the wants and needs of a single person varies tremendously and it is difficult to superimpose the priorities of one on the other and expect an exact match. The best one can hope for is an impasto. How these Ethical Concepts fit in Multi-Cultural Settings Different forms of political conflicts rage over multiculturism. The primary issue is usually the obtaining of social justice by different groups within the society.
In many political situations, the standards of justice within different communities are in flux. These conflicts of justice are often associated with different cultures. Within these cultures, there may be a set of dominating social norms and cultural relativism can seek to link societal justice with these norms. However, she states, most social understandings may not be shared by all members and these dominating mores do not recognise any ethical divergence within it, and therefore cannot be expected to resolve moral conflicts.
(Gutmann, 1993). The execution of justice is hampered by restrictions placed by existing institutions and practices.
Read More