StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

What Did Marx Learn from Rousseau and How Did He Shift the Political Thought - Term Paper Example

Cite this document
Summary
The author identifies what Marx learned from Rousseau. The author states that limiting the powers of government is the only way to defend personal rights, and Constant is worried that Rousseau fails to do this. Rousseau goes so far as to create the error of granting total power to the sovereign…
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER98.2% of users find it useful
What Did Marx Learn from Rousseau and How Did He Shift the Political Thought
Read Text Preview

Extract of sample "What Did Marx Learn from Rousseau and How Did He Shift the Political Thought"

Running Head: WHAT DID MARX LEARN FROM ROUSSEAU What did Marx learn from Rousseau and how did he shift the political thought? Introduction In The Communist Manifesto, Marx argues that the bourgeois reason requires steady and incomplete change in capital materials and, ultimately, society itself. Marx writes, “The bourgeoisie cannot live with no continually revolutionizing the instruments of manufacture, and thus the relations of manufacture, and with them the entire relations of society”. In so doing, Marx shows that there is a close link between economic materials and communal relationships. Political theorists have waged too small notice to the role of literature and the arts in the shaping of political ideals, and of no period is this truer than Rousseau's. This is a great shame, for "conceptions of the nature and reason of art intimately similar man's conceptions of himself and of his fate, and they talk to us in ways far more forceful than abstract theory can do. Critics, when annoying to trace the reason of contemporary political evils, frequently say "It's Rousseau's fault." In a sense they are correct, but it is more generally right to say that the fault lies with an entire multifaceted of popular ideas that were already working influential changes on the public mind from side to side art, literature, and poetry. As it is true that the whole modern democracy group has been permanently shaped by the information of Rousseau that is partially since he so efficiently uttered assumptions that were rising in his time and gave them lasting political expression. They were facts concerning the nature of liberty and democracy that were distorted, and used by others, such as Robespierre, in ways that certainly would have surprised Rousseau. But it is for their vulnerability to use in such way that they must be studied. Rousseau's political facts were at once naive, "mystical," and socialist. (Orwin, 2003, pp 57-61) The Problem Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s extremely public defection from the position of France’s eighteenth-century philosophes has enthused a huge deal of scholarly argument concerning his association to the explanation. He truthfully rejects the explanation itself, or was he just a touchy and suspicious character whose long follow of out of order friendships gave the delusion of an important thinker break that never actually took place. he offer the voice of enlightenment’s own self-critique, or that of a proto-romantic who methodically disavowed as cold and germ-free the disillusioned worldview of his former peers? Graeme Garrard enters this conversation fully conscious that his place is by no means a novel one. Relatively, he aims to offer the most methodical account thus far of Rousseau as “an enemy quite than just a critic of the Enlightenment”. As the theory about political fundamentals suggests, Rousseau directly within the Counter- explanation, interpretation him as a champion of unawareness and rustic ease against the philosophes’ celebration of the progress of information and urbane friendliness. This research a helpful synopsis of Rousseau’s many points of argument with his former peers. By examining Rousseau severely in the context of eighteenth-century philosophical discussions, Garrard avoids the pitfalls of analysis not only Rousseau but also the Enlightenment itself throughout the lens of the French Revolution. Many critics believe this propensity has all too often obscured Rousseau’s proper association to the philosophes, as it drafts him beside his arch-enemy Voltaire to the radical cause. This historicist caution next to sympathetic the ideas of the eighteenth century through its conclusion in the French Revolution are unquestionably just. Yet even when we take away the rebellion from the picture, Rousseau’s fraught association to the information of his former peers remains indefinable, and Garrard’s relentless portrayal of Rousseau as "the Diogenes of his age” relies upon an extremely schematic and literalist analysis of both Rousseau and the explanation. Fundamental Problem That Rousseau Identifies Freedom is almost certainly the mainly significant value coursing through the work over the last twenty-five years. Your question forces everybody to think about ‘why’. The first thing that this research will highlight that there is something roughly temperamental in one’s normative attachments in political hypothesis. This research give psychoanalytical and biographical accounts of political thought attachments, or other accounts, but one of the things that threads jointly approximately all of my work is an anxiety with how to push into the forefront the question of liberty (Riley, 2001, pp 24-26). This means, equally, articulating authority more in terms of power, subjugation, subjectification, and subject configuration, than in terms of inegalitarianism, maldistribution, or even utilization. It’s not that I’m indifferent in these concluding terms, but I’m compelled by the question of power and its inverse, freedom. According to this research, at last, that one can validate such positions. It’s completely reputable to care about equality rather than freedom. It’s perfectly highly regarded to care concerning libertarian freedom as opposed to exacting interest, which is more in communal projects of freedom. Political freedom that involves, amongst other things, supremacy of shared financial and social powers. This is the part of Marx that always been haggard to. There are people who love Marx since of his analysis of the maldistribution of wealth and the democratic promise that communism holds out. That is immense but a lot more involved in the Marxist expression of capital as a mode of power, not only the power of individuals, but power of entire human worlds. the Marx who explains how and why capital controls us quite than us domineering it, and posed the question of what it would denote to have human beings in control of financial life, or at least, to have self-effacing mastery in excess of economic relations. The identical is true of other theorists in the standard of political theory. Freedom is the subject of this research, but nobody can justify that further than saying that it is a little to which I am very emotionally involved and involved. It has been in the backdrop of a massive amount of what I have taught in the last quarter century. A thematic like ‘injured attachments’ came out of the wish to think regarding what occasions the turning away from even the wish for freedom, the repression or dispersal of the will for freedom. Few thinkers have attacked Rousseau by the fury of Benjamin Constant, who begins his philosophy of Politics begins by a sweltering attack on the political thought of Rousseau’s Social Contract. The major push of Constant’s argument is that Rousseau does not take enough steps to defend person freedom. Rousseau’s political project, although nobly intended, sinks unwittingly into despotism. This failure to protect freedom renders Rousseau insufficiently open-minded in Constant’s eyes. (Constant, 2003, pp 14-18) We have to first draw round Constant’s argument, and then look at the merit of this critique. The General Will In this research, there is pure analysis of those aspects of Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s thought for which he has achieved disrepute as a proto-totalitarian. Together in his own time, and still nowadays Rousseau is attacked in the name of freedom. Admittedly, there are many aspects of his consideration that one could without doubt point to when creation such a case. There are a lot of aspects of his consideration that seem upon first glance to be anti-liberal, unfavourable to freedom, and which we therefore connect with being undemocratic and perhaps even totalitarian. A lot of efforts have been made to refute this charge, though, in experts sight, they do so by worsening to address gravely the more difficult aspects of Rousseau’s thought. The propensity is to sight Rousseau as an enthusiastic open-minded whom we can effortlessly bring into the fold as a follower of our notions of a lawful regime. (Bennett, 2003, pp 35-38) It mean to talk about lots of of these aspects of Rousseau’s thought that one might discover, to use the least enjoyable term probable, totalitarian: the lack of check on majoritarianism, civil religion, and the general will. In order to discover these issues, I will look at the job of some of Rousseau’s strongest critics. I will travel around the notion of the universal will, and Constant’s assault on it. This will lead us to a conversation of Rousseau on cause and enlightenment. Then I will look at Rousseau’s future remedies for these failings and the critiques of these remedies. If there is a big class of society that cannot be logical with, it seems as though we have only the options of influence and power as a means of serving them understand the high-quality that they in fact want. Rousseau does not share the explanation view that the many can be made shrewd, and must think throughout what this means. Constant’s sight on public explanation is confused. He admits that there is a class of society powerless to cause, but expresses expect that man will growth. It is this growth that Rousseau questions. If we expect to minimize the demand to force, we have only sub-rational means of serving the people understand the general will. Rousseau, different Constant, offers a sensible solution to this difficulty. The legislator makes recognized the general will, which helps in legislation. (Machiavelli, 1998, pp 91-93) Sovereignty While Garrard appreciates Hulliung’s scholarship, chiefly for its responsive representation of an inside diverse, multifaceted Enlightenment, he however insists that helpful Rousseau inside the explanation itself goes much too far: “Rousseau’s critique of the Enlightenment was so strapping, methodical and bottomless that any attempt to expand the Enlightenment of the philosophes to include it would stretch it to the violation point”. This reading of Rousseau emphasizes significantly different aspects of his thought from Hulliung’s. The “Profession of Faith of the Savoyard Vicar” in Emileoccupies a central position in Garrard’s study, representative Rousseau’s bitter refusal of materialism and resulting dualism: Rousseau’s criticisms of materialism are based on an unequivocal declaration of dualism” (Kelly, 2002, 321-335). Eventually, for Garrard, the “Profession of Faith” is Rousseau’s festivity of sweet lack of knowledge against dishonest knowledge. In the meantime, Hulliung depicts Rousseau as a reasonable materialist himself, not as fundamental as La Mettrie but “with thinkers such as d’Alembert and Voltaire who love to direct out that what we eat in the morning has a direct manner on how we think in the evening” (Benjamin, 2003). Given this investigation, it should come as small revelation that the Profession of Faith receives scant concentration in Hulliung’s book. This dissimilarity in stress points to a deeper difficulty not only with Garrard’s approaches, but also with an exacting sort of approach to the explanation, or quite the so-called Counter-explanation. In other words, the French rebellion just does not stand for the broad will. Constant makes the error of thoughts that a majority of votes constitutes the general will, and this is not so. What makes it general is not arithmetical advantage, but a concern for the well-being of each member of society. (Constant, 2003, pp 19-20) Implications of the General Will Liberalism and Totalitarianism Basically this research work provides such an instance. It wants to protect Rousseau, but devoid of paying grave attention to the implications of some of Rousseau’s less-than-democratic recommendations. This research does a fair job of explanation how his thought is not majoritarian, but simply dismisses the idea that the Legislator is undemocratic: “Neither Rousseau’s idea of the ‘legislator’ nor his theory of a general will can be described as totalitarian in its implications” (Chapman, 2005, p-105). This study of the politician is surely lacking. It argues that the legislator plays no significant role with respect to the general will, and it is indistinct from Chapman’s account what role the legislator would play at all. In fact, he seems to brush aside any thought of the legislator and must look upon his role as insignificant both in the Social Contract and in the role Rousseau wants such a person to play in actual sensible politics. He fails to look at the examples of legislators whom Rousseau mentions or take up the huge task Rousseau describes for such a strange being. Indeed, in this background, Chapman makes no direct orientation to also of the dedicated to this mainly important issue; his place is merely asserted with no reference to the text. (Chapman, 2005, pp 106-109) Though attractive we may find defensive points, it imprecise since it goes too far in the other direction and treats too simply a complex idea. There are lots of aspects of liberal thought to which Rousseau would have had a strong dislike; conversely, there are many aspects of Rousseau’s consideration that we liberals may find disgusting. These are aspects of his consideration that permit investigation. Rousseau’s thought is not totalitarian, and that he intends to define a system of politics that he believes is the only sensible means for establishing, preserving, and protective a polity based on freedom. Rousseau shares numerous of our hopes, expectations, and goals from politics, but he cannot donate to to our means of inward at the decided upon purpose. In other words, Rousseau would discover problems with our exacting liberal sympathetic of democracy, which holds an overly hopeful view of the role that reason can play in politics. Conclusion Limiting the powers of government is the only way to defend person rights and liberty, and Constant is worried that Rousseau fails to do this. In fact, Rousseau goes so far as to create the error of openly granting total power to the sovereign. The spirit of Constant’s assault centers around Rousseau’s use of the general will. Many have argued that the general will grants a limitless authority to the mainstream, and is so totalitarian. George W. F. Hegel would quarrel that “the goal of the Social Contract was the absolute unification of private wills in the concept of the general will.” (Bennett, 2003, p-34)This total amalgamation subordinates will; the citizens will surrender all notions of liberty to the commonwealth, and this amounts to no less than oppression. Constant argues that giving the general will limitless authority will allow convinced members of the state, namely the governing members, to coerce the other members. Rousseau does not quarrel that such a series of events, like the French Revolution, is unfeasible. In its place, Rousseau tells us that in such a case, “there is no longer a general will, and the opinion that prevails is merely a private opinion.” Bibliography Bennett, William J. The Book of Virtues. Simon and Schuster, New York: 2003, pp 34-39. Chapman, John W. Rousseau Totalitarian or Liberal? Columbia University Press, New York: 2005, pp 103-109. Constant, Benjamin. Principles of Politics Applicable to All Governments. Liberty Fund Press, Indianapolis: 2003, pp 13-43. Kelly, Christopher. “‘To Persuade without Convincing’: The Language of Rousseau’s Legislator.” American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 31, No. 2 (May, 2002) 321-335. The Holy Bible, New King James Version. Machiavelli, Niccolò. The Prince. Trans. by Harvey C. Mansfield. University of Chicago Press, Chicago: 1998, pp 87-98. Orwin, Clifford and Nathan Tarcov. The Legacy of Rousseau. University of Chicago Press, Chicago: 2003, pp 56-67. Riley, Patrick. Editor. The Cambridge Companion to Rousseau. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge: 2001, pp 23-34. Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(What Did Marx Learn from Rousseau and How Did He Shift the Political Term Paper, n.d.)
What Did Marx Learn from Rousseau and How Did He Shift the Political Term Paper. Retrieved from https://studentshare.org/politics/1704746-what-did-marx-learn-from-rousseau-and-how-did-he-shift-the-political-thought
(What Did Marx Learn from Rousseau and How Did He Shift the Political Term Paper)
What Did Marx Learn from Rousseau and How Did He Shift the Political Term Paper. https://studentshare.org/politics/1704746-what-did-marx-learn-from-rousseau-and-how-did-he-shift-the-political-thought.
“What Did Marx Learn from Rousseau and How Did He Shift the Political Term Paper”. https://studentshare.org/politics/1704746-what-did-marx-learn-from-rousseau-and-how-did-he-shift-the-political-thought.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF What Did Marx Learn from Rousseau and How Did He Shift the Political Thought

Jean Jacques Rousseau: The Natural Inequality

This passage has little direct reference to the arts and sciences as such, but it is worth quoting as one of his earliest and most succinct protests against existing society; and as an explanation of the main tendencies of his subsequent moral and political thought.... The very smoothness of social polish, which in Rousseau's view derives mainly from intellectual refinement, is, therefore, an obstacle to true social cohesion and integration; and although this mistrust is doubtless born of his own concept of Natural Inequality, it is something which he never abandons, but tends rather to ascribe to all men....
4 Pages (1000 words) Essay

To What Extent is Employee Motivation Staff Employed Affected by Organizational Change

Globalization,… Organizational goals can change, strategies can change, management can change, but how do these impact the employee motivation of Various reasons for organizational and management change have come to light through studies.... Robinson and rousseau (1994) also agree that redundancy leads...
9 Pages (2250 words) Essay

Slavery Throught The World

Most of the modern philosophers are of opinion that human interaction and development of human relations, both are dependent on respective person's perception of power and how they are interpreting scope of such power.... Slavery is an ignominious process against the noble philosophical observation of humanity and natural legal jurisprudence that above all aim at ensuring equality among all human beings, irrespective of their differences in terms of race, cast, creed, ethnicity, skin color and… However, no matter how much humanists and social philosophers have emphasized over the issue of catering the theme of an equal existence but slavery, as one of the major social evils, has always remained as an inequality generating factor, however, it has manifested itself in The history of human civilization is the most explicit document of the fact that corruptible capacity of power can be enhanced to such an elaborate extent that it finally gives birth to a situation of brutal aggression of one man or a community over another less powerful individual or community....
5 Pages (1250 words) Research Paper

The Origins of Inequality

The essence of discussing conjugal society is to distinguish it with that of political society.... Discourse on the Origins of Inequality (second Discourse) ; Polemics ; And, political Economy.... he uses the standard Aristotelian thesis of marriage, that is, a union made for reproduction, sexual desire, and employment.... Moreover, he acknowledges that beyond those elements are mutual affection,… For Locke, marriage is not just utilitarian; there is a factor of love to it....
2 Pages (500 words) Essay

Hobbes and Rousseau on the Creation of Political Authority

This paper "Hobbes and Rousseau on the Creation of Political Authority" discusses the ideas of Hobbes and Rousseau that are both valuable since Hobbes lays down the foundations of why governments are necessary and how a government should be established to protect the governed.... The Ideas of Hobbes and Rousseau are important for all students of political science, history, sociology and even literature because their ideas have formed the basis of almost all modern western democracies....
7 Pages (1750 words) Essay

Main Aspects of Modern Political Thought

This paper outlines Nietzsche's evolution of modern moral values, the problem of maintaining a healthy vibrant civic body based on works of Jean-Jacques rousseau and John Stewart Mill, Machiavelli's and Karl Marx's value of history.... Nietzsche considers these two types of methods of thought integral in the formation of western society.... Nietzsche thought that master morality originated in the strong privileged few while slave morality originated in the underprivileged, weak masses....
8 Pages (2000 words) Essay

French Politics and Culture in the Jean-Jacques Rousseaus View

The changing societal settings, as well as the political scenarios, create a huge impact on the social lifestyle of human.... Furthermore, the author depicts his views about the self-sovereignty that governs the independence and political sovereignty of individuals (Stefanson, 2004).... Through his walks, the author focuses on the different phases of his life that he has faced and his realisation about the self in contrast to the different societal settings (Rousseau, 2011)....
6 Pages (1500 words) Book Report/Review
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us