StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

What goals has liberalism pursued and why have they proved so controversial - Essay Example

Cite this document
Summary
The ideally competitive market in economic theory, where economic representatives are fully informed and ideally rational, is a fiction. It is not in existence, nor is it even compared to, in the real economic practice.Yet this fiction influences greatly upon modern political theory. …
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER99% of users find it useful
What goals has liberalism pursued and why have they proved so controversial
Read Text Preview

Extract of sample "What goals has liberalism pursued and why have they proved so controversial"

What goals has liberalism pursued and why have they proved so controversial The ideally competitive market in economic theory, where economic representatives are fully informed and ideally rational, is a fiction. It is not in existence, nor is it even compared to, in the real economic practice (Macleod 1998, 25). Yet this fiction influences greatly upon modern political theory. The tempting power of the ideal market grounds on its capacity to create elegant and disarmingly easy solutions to difficult problems. We can come to see, for example, how the uncoordinated activity of economic representatives can cause socially desired states of affairs (Moore 1993, 97). In much the same manner, the ideal market gets into normative political philosophy partially because it can be showed as illuminating essential values. Defenders of the market maintain we can get to know much about individual liberty, the encouragement of mutual advantage, and efficiency in the distribution of goods by studying it (Guathier 1986, 119). However, this cardinal limitation of the market for many theorists shows its supposed insensitivity to the demands of egalitarian justice (Ashley 2003, 112). This is partly because modern market societies demonstrate a great deal of social and economic inequality. However, egalitarians have also been inclined to suppose that there is an integral flaw in the ideal of a free market society (Berkowitz 1999, 140). In traditional left-wing critiques, the market has been showed as the opponent of equality on various grounds: it results exploitation; it causes alienation; it is an enemy of genuine freedom; and it is corrosive to the bonds of community (Kautz 1995, 32). It is necessary to notice then that the leading contemporary advocates of egalitarianism, for example Ronald Dworkin (1991), violently defend the use of the ideal market as a theoretical method for the articulation of egalitarian distributive justice and liberal political morality. On the same grounds Judith Shklar's "barebones liberalism" (Whiteside 1999, 501) actually fails to justify either values she proclaimed or liberal ideals of equality. In the end of her career, Shklar made her liberalism specific and took it in an egalitarian direction. She did so by launching skeptical issues at the certainties usually used to rationalize inequalities. While defending equality she ended up making empirical and ethical affirmations that her skepticism had expelled, providing strong proof for the conclusion that skepticism alone is insufficient for creating an egalitarian politics (Tomasi 2000, 46). In this direction of her thought, Shklar defined what Isaiah Berlin calls a "plurality of values." Like Berlin's, her way of thinking affirms "the permanent possibility of inescapable conflict between values" (Berlin 1990, 80) Although Shklar in some way agreed with the liberalism of Hobbes and Locke, she doubts the premises of their arguments (Dagger 1997, 98). The problem is that real consent - as opposed to the consent imagined in tales of the social contract - is elusive (Plaw 2002, 267). The fact of the matter, Shklar (1986) suggests, is that liberalism rests on moral intuitions that are plural, vague and controversial. All along liberal universalism was an illusion. "To a large extent," she concludes, "it was European ethnocentrism and indifference to historical variety and change that made discourse relevant to all' seem plausible in the first place" (Shklar 1967, 278). The difficulties befalling her "barebones liberalism" are the same as those that debilitate the "agonistic liberalism" of theorists like Joseph Raz and Isaiah Berlin (Gottfried 1999, 211). Like Shklar, these theorists propose a defense of liberty grounded in a "radical choice between incommensurables," to use John Gray's phrase (cited in Hardin 1999, 162). This is a choice that can only be settled in political competition - rather than in a putatively rational consensus. But Gray argues convincingly that accepting value pluralism does not entail privileging a liberal political order. It implies "theorizing liberal institutions and practices as particular forms of life having no universal authority whatever" (Gray 1995, 133). If values and interpretations are radically plural, rooted in different cultures and historical experiences, then one cannot even claim that a regime dedicated to individual liberty is preferable. Liberal individualism and toleration are only aspects of a contingent cultural form (Kloppenberg 1998, 102). Gray's (1995) "post-liberalism" ends in a plea for us to learn to live with other communities' ways of life, "each with their characteristic, and often exclusionary excellences, virtues, and goods." That candid reference to "exclusionary excellences, virtues, and goods" reminds us that radical pluralism offers no decisive support to liberal values of social inclusiveness and equal respect for individuals (Hardin 1999, 167). It is reasonable to suppose that support by liberals for actual free market arrangements as well as antipathy towards alternative economic models can be traced, at least in part, to the use in liberal theory of ideal models of market interaction (Chan 2002, 39). Whether we should be enthusiastic, from the point of view of justice, about extensive reliance on free market economic arrangements depends partly on the appropriateness of theoretically linking the market and justice (Macleod 1998, 210). The market now occupies a central place in modern liberal democracies and its machinations have a profound effect on the character of the communities in which we live. Moreover, the global dominance of the market is increasing. Thus, for example, Dworkin's account of liberal theory (1981) begins with the controversial but compelling claim that all theories of political morality can and should be construed as interpretations of an abstract but fundamental requirement that all persons be treated with equal concern and respect. The now famous equal concern and respect formula captures the idea that "the interests of the members of the community matter and matter equally" (Dworkin 1991, 24). This abstract egalitarian thesis is said to provide a common point of departure for all plausible theories of political morality. For Dworkin, developing a theory of political morality consists largely in developing a plausible and compelling interpretation of the fundamental egalitarian demand (Fonte 1995, 49). This involves furnishing an account of people's interests "most comprehensively construed' and determining what follows from 'supposing these interests matter equally" (Dworkin 1981, 287). Dworkin has claimed that the plausible forms of utilitarianism, libertarianism, Rawlsian contractarianism, and equal welfare theories can and should be represented as interpretations of the abstract egalitarian ideal (Dworkin 1981, 246 cited in Kymlcika 1989, 173). He also thinks there are decisive objections to these theories qua interpretations of the egalitarian thesis (Haas 1997, 45). The idea that some principle of equality has a fundamental role to play in political philosophy is, of course, an old and familiar claim. However, it is only in the last twenty years or so that systematic efforts have been made to articulate explicitly egalitarian conceptions of justice (Dyzenhaus 1998, 59). Much of the impetus for the exploration of the idea of equality can, of course, be traced to the work of Rawls (1971). His suggestion that the central idea of distributive justice is that there is a strong presumption that primary goods should be distributed equally has generated remarkable interest in the idea of distributional equality (cited in Macleod 1998, 217). Many theorists agree that equality must be accepted as a fundamental principle of distribution but they disagree both over how equality should be understood and what exactly justice requires be distributed equally (Moore 1993, 72). As Amartya Sen says we want an answer to the question: Equality of what (Sen 1992, 251). We need a richer account of the egalitarian ideal and how it may be realized. A number of different competing theories have tried to supply an answer to this problem. Even a cursory review reveals the lively debate surrounding the meaning of equality (Heideking 2002, 97). Sen argues that Rawls's focus on primary goods is too narrow. He suggests that we should focus on a notion of basic capabilities and this leads him to a conception of "basic capability equality" (Sen 1992, 230). Richard Arneson believes that what egalitarians should really care about is welfare, but he also believes a conception of distributive equality must be sensitive to certain considerations of individual responsibility. As a consequence, he develops a theory of 'equality opportunity for welfare' (Arneson 1989 cited in Plaw 2002, 257). G. A. Cohen has reservations about Arneson's proposal and develops his own variant of it called 'equal access to advantage' (Cohen 1989, 911). Dworkin (1991) has argued against a variety of versions of the view that it is welfare that egalitarians should aim to equalize. All versions of equality of welfare are, in Dworkin's (1981) view, defective conceptions of equality. Instead he argues that it is resources that should be distributed equally. All these theories are interesting and important but in many respects Dworkin's theory stands alone in the field (Chan, 2002, 129). What is noteworthy about Dworkin's contribution to egalitarian theory is its sheer breadth and depth. Where other egalitarian theories provide accounts of distributional equality, Dworkin uses his conception of equality as a basis on which to construct a comprehensive theory of political morality (Macleod 1998, 115). His remarkable achievement has been to offer an explanation of how the apparently disparate ideals embraced by liberalism can be systematically articulated and defended through the adoption of an egalitarian conception of distributive justice (Tomasi 2000, 62). As we have already indicated, at the heart of this theory of equality lies the ideal market. It is crucial to emphasize that the market does not appear in Dworkin's theory simply as a useful heuristic device. Rather it is intrinsic to the very interpretation of equality (Hardin 1999, 71). As Dworkin puts it, "the best theory of equality presupposes some actual or hypothetical market in justifying a particular distribution of goods and opportunities" (Dworkin 1981, 38). Yet the initial interpretation of the abstract egalitarian thesis does not begin with the market but with an account of the nature of our most fundamental interests (King 1999, 65). The failure of egalitarian theory in the past to accommodate responsibility has, in my view, substantially undermined its appeal both philosophically and politically by leaving egalitarianism vulnerable to libertarian critiques which place great emphasis on the moral and political significance of choice. Though libertarians are apt to exaggerate the degree to which entitlement is a matter of individual choice, they are right to insist that an account of justice which ignores or marginalizes responsibility for our own lives is unsatisfactory (Kautz 1995, 44). WORKS CITED Ashley, Susan A. 2003. Making Liberalism Work: The Italian Experience, 1860-1914. Westport, CT: Praeger. Berlin, I. 1990. The Crooked Timber of Humanity. London: John Murray, 80 Chan, Sylvia. 2002. Liberalism, Democracy, and Development. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Cohen, J. A. 1989. On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice. Ethics, 99/ 4: 906-44. Dagger, Richard Johnson. 1997. Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press. Dworkin, Ronald. 1981. What Is Equality Part I: Equality of Welfare; Part II: Equality of Resources. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10, 3-4: 185246, 283-345. Dworkin, Ronald. 1991. Foundations of Liberal Equality. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Fonte, John. 1995. Ill Liberalism. National Review, 6 February, 48. Gottfried, Paul Edward. 1999. After Liberalism: Mass Democracy in the Managerial State. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Gray, J. 1995. Enlightenment's Wake: Politics and Culture at the Close of the Modern Age. New York: Routledge, 133. Guathier, D. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Haas, Ernst B. 1997. Nationalism, Liberalism, and Progress. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Hardin, Russell. 1999. Liberalism, Constitutionalism, and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kautz, Steven. 1995. Liberalism and Community. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Kerlinger, Fred N. 1984. Liberalism and Conservatism: The Nature and Structure of Social Attitudes. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. King, Desmond. 1999. In the Name of Liberalism : Illiberal Social Policy in the USA and Britain. New York: Oxford University Press. Kloppenberg, James T. 1998. The Virtues of Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press. Kymlicka, W. 1989. Liberalism, Community, and Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bibliography Avnon, Dan and Avner De-Shalit, eds. 1999. Liberalism and Its Practice. London: Routledge. Barry, Bane. 1989. Theories of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Berkowitz, Peter. 1999. Virtue and the Making of Modern Liberalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Dyzenhaus, David, ed. 1998. Law as Politics: Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Freeden, Michael. 1986. Liberalism Divided: A Study in British Political Thought, 1914-1939. Oxford: Oxford University. Heideking, Jrgen, James A. Henretta, and Peter Becker, eds. 2002. Republicanism and Liberalism in America and the German States, 1750-1850. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Sinopoli, Richard C. 1992. The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue. New York: Oxford University Press. Macleod, Colin M. 1998. Liberalism, Justice, and Markets: A Critique of Liberal Equality. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Moore, Margaret. 1993. Foundations of Liberalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Plaw, Avery. 2002. The Limited Compatibility of Liberalism and Pluralism: Against the General Incompatibility Thesis. International Journal of Politics and Ethics 2, no. 4: 257. Sen, Amartya. 1992. Inequality Reexamined. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Shklar, J. 1986. ed. Lucash, Frank S. Injustice, Injury, Inequality: An Introduction. Justice and Equality Here and Now. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 14. Shklar, J. ed. Spitz, David. 1967. Facing Up to Intellectual Pluralism. Political Theory and Social Change. New York: Atherton Press, 278-79. Tomasi, John. 2000. Liberalism beyond Justice: Citizens, Society, and the Boundaries of Political Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Whiteside, Kerry H. 1999. Justice Uncertain: Judith Shklar on Liberalism, Skepticism, and Equality. Polity 31, no. 3: 501. Ashley, Susan A. 2003. Making Liberalism Work: The Italian Experience, 1860-1914. Westport, CT: Praeger. Berlin, I. 1990. The Crooked Timber of Humanity. London: John Murray, 80 Chan, Sylvia. 2002. Liberalism, Democracy, and Development. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Cohen, J. A. 1989. On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice. Ethics, 99/ 4: 906-44. Dagger, Richard Johnson. 1997. Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press. Dworkin, Ronald. 1981. What Is Equality Part I: Equality of Welfare; Part II: Equality of Resources. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10, 3-4: 185246, 283-345. Dworkin, Ronald. 1991. Foundations of Liberal Equality. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Fonte, John. 1995. Ill Liberalism. National Review, 6 February, 48. Gottfried, Paul Edward. 1999. After Liberalism: Mass Democracy in the Managerial State. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Gray, J. 1995. Enlightenment's Wake: Politics and Culture at the Close of the Modern Age. New York: Routledge, 133. Guathier, D. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Haas, Ernst B. 1997. Nationalism, Liberalism, and Progress. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Hardin, Russell. 1999. Liberalism, Constitutionalism, and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kautz, Steven. 1995. Liberalism and Community. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Kerlinger, Fred N. 1984. Liberalism and Conservatism: The Nature and Structure of Social Attitudes. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. King, Desmond. 1999. In the Name of Liberalism : Illiberal Social Policy in the USA and Britain. New York: Oxford University Press. Kloppenberg, James T. 1998. The Virtues of Liberalism. New York: Oxford University Press. Kymlicka, W. 1989. Liberalism, Community, and Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(“What goals has liberalism pursued and why have they proved so Essay”, n.d.)
Retrieved de https://studentshare.org/politics/1503410-what-goals-has-liberalism-pursued-and-why-have-they-proved-so-controversial
(What Goals Has Liberalism Pursued and Why Have They Proved so Essay)
https://studentshare.org/politics/1503410-what-goals-has-liberalism-pursued-and-why-have-they-proved-so-controversial.
“What Goals Has Liberalism Pursued and Why Have They Proved so Essay”, n.d. https://studentshare.org/politics/1503410-what-goals-has-liberalism-pursued-and-why-have-they-proved-so-controversial.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF What goals has liberalism pursued and why have they proved so controversial

Class Does Matter: Social Background Determines Success of Pupils

Some of these standard mechanisms included representation of parents on governing bodies, parental choice and creating a link between student enrolment numbers and school funding so as to bridge the gap.... Keeping in view all these issues, a nationwide standard curriculum was introduced by the government for the students in the age group of 7-16, so as to ensure that every student studied a minimum component of the curriculum (DCSF, 2009).... The policy makers have also been concerned about the existence of poor basic skills found in the UK workforce, in comparison to other nations, especially amongst the younger population....
15 Pages (3750 words) Essay

The New Labour. Young People and Youth Offending

It is for this reason why the New Labour has been tugged into critical controversial issues that otherwise had not been associated with them.... Although the discipline of social policy to the New Labour Government proved to be an applied social science where they felt the need to draw upon youth sociology in the context of addressing youth welfare issues, but the New Labour Reforms in context with the Youth Justice System lacked the approach which their predecessors adopted....
10 Pages (2500 words) Book Report/Review

International relations in theory and practice

hus, the position of the state as a principal actor represents one of the most controversial aspects of IR theory.... ven so, the first valuable theory writings belong to XX st century.... Social and economic development were key factors for two seemingly antagonistic phenomena: on the one hand, there was the strengthening of the state power, and on the other hand, once World War I came to an end, the international system was faced with new actors exercising power of decision-making; the globalisation of political, economic, social and cultural relations gave rise to international actors, multinational companies, international organizations (the League of Nations, and then, the United Nations), integrating organisation (process which automatically implies a delegation of sovereignty to a higher level); among non-state actors, especially after 9/11 one can also mention terrorist organisations and "the new form of trans-national terrorism which is far more complex and difficult to monitor, analyse, and combat ()some claim that this 'new' terrorism is displacing the older forms of terrorism and has now become the major threat" (Wilkinson, 2001)....
11 Pages (2750 words) Essay

Summary of Ten Readings

The formation of the UN (even though controversial) is one of the biggest factors.... They want cooperation from them, so they can help rehabilitate the regions they kept in slavery for centuries.... so even if they consider it a  repudiation to amend what they had done previously  keeping colonies of the area which are the third world the third world countries, it will help them in many ways.... Despite so many conflicts occurring the world, there has not been a Third World War, the reason is more than just coincidence....
8 Pages (2000 words) Essay

Study of Civil Societies in Saudi Arabia

This has been so for long time particularly since the Roman Catholic Church concentrated its focus on marginalized areas and politically unstable regions.... Notably, the review process not only proved… The research that undertakes this role is applied policy research that is required to gather specific information and has the potential to create actionable 2009: 73).... The realm of civil society in Saudi was for long a neglected field and least studied have been conducted in this region among others of Middle East and GCC countries....
9 Pages (2250 words) Essay

The President and the Supreme Court - George Bush-Clarence Thomas

The nomination of President Bush of Thomas Clarence in 1991 and the subsequent hearing in the judicial commission proved to be the most controversial in the nation's judicial confirmation history, a controversy sparked by the sexual harassment testimony of Thomas' colleague.... As author Clarence Lusane put it “With the nomination of Thomas, George Bush found himself in a win-win situation: If the nomination succeeded, then Bush would have the ultra-conservative he desired....
13 Pages (3250 words) Research Paper

Divorce in the USA

However, there is a couple of key controversial issues that have been identified to pose a threat to the existence of a firmly solid family fabric.... The issue appears to have multiple causes those together point towards changing societal trends.... Loss of intimacy and renewed pursuit for careers and professions appear to have replaced the traditional definition of family.... A few studies have shown that there is consistent deterioration in the family structure and social fabric continues to get eroded....
7 Pages (1750 words) Literature review

The United States Healthcare System: the Continuous Inputs Rise

In order to prevent or have an inexpensive treatment, situations often go out of hand and lead to a health crisis thereby leading to increased treatment costs.... In order to understand why our healthcare inputs continue to rise as against the outputs such as life expectancy which remain constant, we should acknowledge the significance distinction between total and marginal contribution.... This saying reflects on the fact that just as any other market, healthcare is also subject to market forces but it is due to its emotive nature the benefits it provides, that a kind of a balance has been maintained between the market forces and the social needs of the population....
8 Pages (2000 words) Article
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us