StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

The Humean Problem of Evil - Coursework Example

Cite this document
Summary
The paper "The Humean Problem of Evil" focuses on the main peculiarities of the problem of evil in Hume's philosophy. Many times, the elucidations of Hume’s philosophy of religion are made against the foundation of a broader understanding of his philosophical aims…
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER93.5% of users find it useful

Extract of sample "The Humean Problem of Evil"

The Humean Problem of Evil Student’s Name Professor’s Name Date of Submission Introduction Many times, the elucidations of Hume’s philosophy of religion are made against the foundation of a broader understanding of his philosophical aims. Elucidations of Hume's rationality of religion are regularly made against the foundation of more broad understandings of his philosophical aims.1 From this point of view, it is not unordinary to view Hume's perspectives on religion in terms of naturalism and the skepticism that prominently feature in his 1739–40’s Treatise of Human instinct, his most ambitious and first ever philosophical work. As per a prior scholarly agreement, predominant all through a great part of the 20th century, Hume removed nearly all the material in the Treatise which was focused on religion since he was on edge to abstain from provoking the religious foundation. Later on in his later works, starting with the 1748’s Enquiry Concerning Human Comprehension, Hume started to present his perspectives regarding this matter in a direct and substantial way. This ends in his 1757’s Natural History of Religion together with the 1779’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion- the two of them are focused on religion. On this prior scholarly account, the connection between these different works is that the late works on religion are an application and extension of the naturalistic and skeptical principles which Hume advanced in his prior works.2 David Hume's different works focusing on problems issues of religion are amongst the most influential and vital contributions on this subject. Hume in these works develops a precise, incredulous investigation of the philosophical establishments of different religious frameworks. Whatever understanding a person takes of Hume's logic in entirety, it is undoubtedly true that one of his most essential philosophical goals is discrediting the dogmas and tenets of customary theistic conviction. However, there are a number some significant points of disagreement about the precise degree and nature of Hume’s irreligious objectives. Amongst them, the most vital of these is if the skeptical position of Hume prompts him to a see what can be correct defines as “atheism.” The Problem of Evil The problem of evil argument is trying to prove that God does not exist because there if suffering. I believe that God exists, but he allows for suffering for a multitude of reasons. The problem with the evil argument says that if God exists he is defined as an all-good and all-powerful being. If God is all-good, then he would wish to stop all anguish that he could. If God is omnipotent, then he would have the capacity to bar all suffering that he wants to.3 Therefore if God exists, there would be no suffering. But there is, in fact, suffering in the world. So God does not exist. I think that the conclusion of this argument is incorrect. Another way of looking at this argument is that yes God is all-good and all-powerful so he knows about suffering and could stop it, but one objection to this argument would be that God does exist he just has a reason to allow for suffering. The world where people have free will is better than the world without free will. Some people might ask why we can’t have free will with no suffering. The world with no suffering means people would not have choices. Another reason why God might allow suffering is because God is giving us the opportunity for us to make morally significant choices. Suffering and evil also allows for “second-order” goods such as charity and allows for people to develop morals and grow as human beings. Among the many things that Philo uses to attack empirical theism is the criticism of the problem of evil. Issues of evil in its conventional form is viewed as an obstacle to the regular notion of God. Provided that evil is present in the earth, the reasoning line reads, who are we to form an inference on God? He either wants to bar evil and lacks the capacity. It means he is not ceasing, and He is not interminably powerful, or he can prevent evil, but he wishes not to. In this situation, we could infer that he is not infinitely good; or, ultimately, maybe he does not simply understand the ideal procedure of running the world, and this means case he isn’t interminably wise. Theists wish to argue that God is forever wise, good, and powerful and therefore the problem of evil leaves serious challenges to them. The Humean Problem of Evil For years, the Problem of Evil has bothered human beings prompting Christians to have a feeling of being under pressure to protect their Lord from unbelievers’ criticisms. Many times, Christians discard the Problem of Evil, arguing that it is a parody of God’s character. The problem of Evil, however, will keep on being a valid criticism leveled against Christianity and for this reason, it should not overlook.4 The Argument from Evil by Hume, as an analytically, an inferential and comprehensive argument is one of the solid depictions of the argument and is not well repudiated by theodicies eliminating God from the obligation for the existence of evil. The Problem of Wickedness is a standout amongst the regularly referenced obstacles to Christianity. Its rationale is apparently irrefutable and inference profoundly particular. At its center, it holds that the misery proves for the duration of one's life appears to shout out against the presence of a Divine being who is both almighty and benevolent. This concept has been there for years, Hume references Epicurus as having stated: "Is [God] ready to counteract detestable, however not capable? At that point He is barren. It is safe to say that he is capable, yet not willing? At that point he is vindictive. It is safe to say that he is both capable and willing? Whence then is detestable?" (Hume [1] 134). After a long while, this contention has taken a wide range of structures, each with its weakness and strengths. Hume is not especially worried about this solid adaptation of the issue of shrewdness. Philo reveals to us that insofar as we concede that God is inconceivable there is no issue here by any means: we should just permit that while God's limitless flawlessness can, truth be told, be accommodated with the nearness of shrewdness on the planet, we have no clue how this compromise may happen. The main time the issue of insidiousness truly turns into an issue, he attests, is the point at which we attempt to claim that God is emphatically comparable to an individual.5 On the off chance that God is anything like an individual, and can be judged by human models of equity, benevolence, and empathy, then he can't be all great. In this sense, the customary form of the issue of fiendishness introduces a genuine issue for the exact theist seeing that the observational theist puts stock in a humanized God. The real concern of Hume with the problem of evil, be that as it may, is somewhat not the same as this conventional concern about compromise. Hume is not all that keen on the issue as a test to the conventional God’s notion, as he is on the issue as a square to any derivations that we could come up with about God's ethical quality. Since there is a lot of evil is in our world, Hume contends, we can't take a gander at our universe and sensibly deduce from the proof that God is endlessly astute, great, and effective. We can't even sensibly close from the proof that God is respectably powerful, wise and good. If we somehow happened to attempt to make any inferences about God's inclination simply from the confirmation managed us by nature the main justified inference would be that God is unconcerned amongst evil and good—that he is ethically impartial. The contention from plan then in addition to some other kind of contention for pragmatic theism can't in any way shape or form function as a contention that enlightens us concerning God's ethical quality. God is ethical in nature, and the shortcomings make empirical theism appear to be entirely sad. The Evidential Problem of Evil in Christianity The evidential issue of evil is the aspect of judging evil. Assuming presence of evil, it proceeds to decide the degree the presence of evil (or particular kinds, cases, amounts, or appropriations of evil). It comprises proof of the existence of God, which is to state, a creature impeccable in goodness, knowledge, and power. Evidential contentions from the evil endeavor to demonstrate that, immediately when we reserve any confirmation there may be in backing the presence of God, it turns out to be improbable, in the event not exceedingly far-fetched, that the world was made and is represented by an omniscient, all-powerful, and completely great being. Such contentions are not to be mistaken for consistent claims from fiendishness that has the more aggressive goal of demonstrating which in the world is malicious, it is coherently unimaginable—and not only far-fetched—that God is there.6 The contention from the problem of evil is the assertion that an almighty, all-knowing, and flawlessly great God would at any point not permit any—or certain sorts of—suffering or evil to happen.7 Not at all like the sensible contention from the evil that holds that the presence of God (so characterized) is consistently contrary to some well-established truth about evil, has the probabilistic (or evidential) contention from evil argued that some well-established reality about evil is proof of the presence of God. For example, one adaptation of the claim explains that the organic part of agony and delight is a great deal more probable on naturalism than belief in a higher power such as Paul Draper. Different variants of the evidential contention yield that God could have an ethically adequate purpose behind permitting particular evils to happen—for instance, to guarantee that some more prominent great is accomplished as an outcome of evil. Proponents include in any case; God would just permit as much shrewd or enduring as is essential keeping in mind the end goal to accomplish more exceptional products.8 In any case, when we take a gander at our general surroundings, we find predominant examples of precisely needless insidiousness—trivial disasters from which no more prominent great appears to exist. As indicated by advocates, the presence of unwanted evil gives solid confirmation that God as customarily characterized is not there as stated by William Rowe. Hume’s skeptical position The concession of Hume that God's and evil presence are harmonious may resemble (another) "withdrawal" from a more grounded skeptical position. The noteworthiness of this concession ought not to be overstated. While the skeptic can't demonstrate that there does without a doubt exist some superfluous fiendishness on the planet, it is by and by conceivable to demonstrate that this perspective of things is not the slightest bit preposterous.9 Hume depicts a fourfold list of reasons for fiendishness in this world none of which "seem to human reason, at all extent, fundamental or inescapable." Humes poses the question, for instance, why the creation of an animal is not entirely animated by delight, as it seems to be "obviously conceivable to bear on the matter of existence with no agony." Comparably, why could God not have been more liberal in furnishing his animals with better gifts for their happiness and survival? Once more, why does nature keep running into such extremes in connection to cold and warmth, downpours, winds, et cetera? Without a doubt, could things have been organized so that these extremes and their disastrous outcomes could be maintained a strategic distance? Finally, Hume inquires as to why God fails to act through specific decisions to counteract particular disasters and catastrophes (for instance, why not guarantee there is no tempest blowing when an armada is out adrift)? In every one of these cases, Hume awards, there may "be great reasons, why provision intervenes not in this way; but rather they are obscure to us." The ramifications of this is not quite recently that we have no motivation to deduce the presence of an interminably intense and great God however that we have an extensive purpose behind questioning it. The evidential issue of shrewdness advances the single amount of the actualities about detestable as its beginning proof. It doesn't infer this demonstrates that God does not exist, as the consistent issue did. It observes this single amount of the considerable number of certainties about abhorrent as extremely solid proof against the presence of God. Exceptionally solid confirmation is as yet not a proof. Obviously, if it is extremely solid confirmation, and that proof can't be countered with option clarifications, then maybe nobody ought to have faith in God.10 The Humean Argument from Evil is presented way similar to a kind of dilemma. As Hume defines in his contention, God is conventional Christian God, who is not only omnipotent but also omnibenevolent. His initial argument says that (1) in the event that evil exists, then either God enabled wickedness to exist or He can't keep evil’s presence. Also, [as we understand inductively through experience], (2) shrewd or enduring exists. Here Hume portrays a problem. If God has permitted malicious then God is not omnibenevolent.11 So also if God can't anticipate abhorrently then God is not all-powerful. Hume infers that a God who is both omnibenevolent and supreme can't exist in all actuality. (Hume [Q2] 298). Hume does not deny the existence of any God but instead raises doubts over the possibility of the Christian God existing in reality. As a deductive argument, Hume’s version of the argument from evil is inherently stronger than inductive arguments. Many of the evidentialist versions of the Problem of Evil are inductive in structure. Rather than using logical contradictions to assert the non-existence of the Christian God, inductive arguments reason from probability. While conceding that the existence of God may be logically consistent with the existence of evil, inductive arguments reason that the likelihood of this is exceedingly low.12 However, these arguments are not immediately conclusive. Firstly, by basing the argument on available evidence, this always allows for the existence of evidence that is of yet unknown. Though there may no known evidence to contradict the argument, this does not mean this evidence does not exist. In contrast, valid deductive arguments with true premises produce conclusions that are necessarily true with absolute certainty13. Secondly, arguments from probability require at least a basic understanding of the object or action of which it describes. As it is difficult to quantify what may be regarded as evidence of the metaphysical, any notion of probability is hard to measure.14 Deductive arguments answer questions of possibility rather than probability and thus are not subject to these criticisms. Within the class of deductive arguments, Hume’s argument is highly persuasive due to its methodical analysis of each evident possibility. The Logical Problem of Evil, another deductive form of the argument, takes the nature of God as omnibenevolent and omnipotent as a set and argues that this notion is inconsistent with the existence of evil. It does not provide an explanation for where the inconsistency lies specific, or address possible ways of reconciling the premises. Hume’s dilemma is clear by showing precisely how the omnibenevolence and omnipotence of God and the existence of evil are directly at odds with each other, and how attempts to reconcile these are incoherent.15 It is imperative that Christians can disprove any claims to inconsistency raised by Hume. “If Christianity is logically incoherent, no amount of positive, factual evidence can save its truth. The internal inconsistency would itself render Christian faith intellectually unacceptable” (Bahnsen 166). Christians have for centuries aimed to refute the problem by refuting the premises. No Christian would refute that God is completely good, and thus this premise is left untouched. Some Christians do refute the second premise, by providing a theodicy limiting God’s omnipotence. Commonly referred as the Free Will defense, one tenant of the theological position of Open Theism is that God does not know beforehand the decisions of man’s free will. Open Theists argue that “in order for the free will to be truly free, the future free will choices of individuals cannot be known ahead of time by God” (Slick).16 The most common view of Open Theism is Involuntary Nescience, wherein God knows everything that can be knowable. Affiliates to these beliefs would argue that because the future has not yet happened, it is impossible to know the future with absolute certainty, and God is unable to act on what cannot be known, removing evil from God’s responsibility. Similarly, affiliates of Voluntary Nescience argue that this robs God of His omniscience, and would posit that though God could know everything, he voluntary chooses not to know about the future. They reason that because of love and respect for mankind, God withholds from himself all of the future’s details. Thus there is nothing God is unable to know, but rather he simply ignores some information.17 Both viewpoints agree that God has not predestined all things, but rather works in the present, making decisions as events, evil or good, occur. Open Theism then seeks to provide an explanation for God, while being omnipotent, is unable to act in such a way to stop evil. This position, however, robs Christians of confidence in God. Douglas Wilson explains, “This view of God is supposed to engender comfort and hope on the part of believers; but in fact, it destroys the very foundation that the Bible establishes for trusting God” (Wilson [2]). Wilson goes on to argue that God is not a “Cosmic Gambler” who gambles that his creation would choose to love and trust him. In fact, billions, of people have done the opposite. Why should we place our faith in a God whose desires have been thwarted throughout all of history? Furthermore, as with any theodicy, these views claim to have an insightful understanding of God’s reasoning, which is certainly disputed and can appear rather pretentious. Hume’s deductive problem of evil avoids many of the accusations raised against inductive arguments, is especially evident by showing the how its premises are inconsistent with the nature of the Christian God and is not able to be refuted by theodicies which attempt to make God not responsible for the existence of evil.18 While Hume admits that his argument does not prove the non-existence of any God, there is little basis for believing that an omnibenevolent and omnipotent God exists given such evidence of evil. Conclusion The inclination of evil discussion of Hume, in both the Dialogues and the Enquiry, is insisting the evil reality and the questions that this throws on any claim that the magnificence, amicability and world’s order furnishes us with clear confirmation that a limitlessly capable and great being made and administers it. Hume’s argument as we have noticed misses the mark of specifically denying that God exists in the light of the fact that there is pointless shrewdness in this world. However, what Hume's arguments demonstrate is that whereas it is conceivable that the reality evil is steady with God’s existence, this leaves theism with a vast and noteworthy issues that unanswered. The tremendous level of this world’s evil and the immense scope of structures that it takes are difficult to justify or clarify from our human point of view (that is, given the cutoff points of human comprehension). Consequently, there is no reason for concluding the presence of an endlessly intense and great God in the face of opposite proof of this sort — confirm that furnishes us with extensive justification for questioning this hypothesis or conjecture. In reality, David Hume has contributed than other philosophers to the advancement of an analytical custom in the philosophy of religion. I trust that Hume has offered a satisfactory answer several problems. At a basic level, he has clarified what a person may be attempting or demanding in an ‘answer’ to the issue. Also, he demonstrates that theists ought to accept particular burdens of proof- in spite of the fact that theists have a purpose of endeavoring a broad answer to the problem of evil in comparison to what Hume appears to argue. Bibliography Allan, Leslie. "The Problem of Evil." URL=< http://www. RationalRealm. com/philosophy/metaphysics/problem-of-evil. html (2015). Beebe, James R. "Logical problem of evil." (2003). Benton, Matthew A., John Hawthorne, and Yoaav Isaacs. "Evil and evidence." Oxford studies in the philosophy of religion 7 (2016): 1-31. Box, Mark A. The Suasive Art of David Hume. Princeton University Press, 2014. Campbell Jr, Ronnie Paul. "Mere Christian Theism and the Problem of Evil: Toward A Trinitarian Perichoretic Theodicy." Ph.D. diss., Liberty University, 2015. Chattopadhyay, Subhasis. "Review of Evil In Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy." (2016). Collier, Brady J. God, and fruitless evil: A holistic response to the problem of evil. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary, 2015. Craig, William Lane. "The Problem of Evil.”." Reasonable Fath (2014). Dougherty, Trent, and Scott Cleveland. "The Problem of Evil." (2014). Eroukhmanoff, Clara. "A Critical Contribution to the “Security-Religion” Nexus: Going Beyond the Analytical." (2016): 366-378. Friesenhahn, Jacob H. The Trinity and theodicy: the Trinitarian theology of von Balthasar and the problem of evil. Routledge, 2016. Saunders, Ben. "King Lear and the Problem of Evil." The Routledge Companion to Literature and Religion (2016): 213. Thomas, David E. "An Unconventional Look at the Challenge of Theodicy." Journal of the Adventist Theological Society 26, no. 2 (2015): 11. Van Inwagen, Peter. The problem of evil. Oxford University Press on Demand, 2008. Read More

Another way of looking at this argument is that yes God is all-good and all-powerful so he knows about suffering and could stop it, but one objection to this argument would be that God does exist he just has a reason to allow for suffering. The world where people have free will is better than the world without free will. Some people might ask why we can’t have free will with no suffering. The world with no suffering means people would not have choices. Another reason why God might allow suffering is because God is giving us the opportunity for us to make morally significant choices.

Suffering and evil also allows for “second-order” goods such as charity and allows for people to develop morals and grow as human beings. Among the many things that Philo uses to attack empirical theism is the criticism of the problem of evil. Issues of evil in its conventional form is viewed as an obstacle to the regular notion of God. Provided that evil is present in the earth, the reasoning line reads, who are we to form an inference on God? He either wants to bar evil and lacks the capacity.

It means he is not ceasing, and He is not interminably powerful, or he can prevent evil, but he wishes not to. In this situation, we could infer that he is not infinitely good; or, ultimately, maybe he does not simply understand the ideal procedure of running the world, and this means case he isn’t interminably wise. Theists wish to argue that God is forever wise, good, and powerful and therefore the problem of evil leaves serious challenges to them. The Humean Problem of Evil For years, the Problem of Evil has bothered human beings prompting Christians to have a feeling of being under pressure to protect their Lord from unbelievers’ criticisms.

Many times, Christians discard the Problem of Evil, arguing that it is a parody of God’s character. The problem of Evil, however, will keep on being a valid criticism leveled against Christianity and for this reason, it should not overlook.4 The Argument from Evil by Hume, as an analytically, an inferential and comprehensive argument is one of the solid depictions of the argument and is not well repudiated by theodicies eliminating God from the obligation for the existence of evil. The Problem of Wickedness is a standout amongst the regularly referenced obstacles to Christianity.

Its rationale is apparently irrefutable and inference profoundly particular. At its center, it holds that the misery proves for the duration of one's life appears to shout out against the presence of a Divine being who is both almighty and benevolent. This concept has been there for years, Hume references Epicurus as having stated: "Is [God] ready to counteract detestable, however not capable? At that point He is barren. It is safe to say that he is capable, yet not willing? At that point he is vindictive.

It is safe to say that he is both capable and willing? Whence then is detestable?" (Hume [1] 134). After a long while, this contention has taken a wide range of structures, each with its weakness and strengths. Hume is not especially worried about this solid adaptation of the issue of shrewdness. Philo reveals to us that insofar as we concede that God is inconceivable there is no issue here by any means: we should just permit that while God's limitless flawlessness can, truth be told, be accommodated with the nearness of shrewdness on the planet, we have no clue how this compromise may happen.

The main time the issue of insidiousness truly turns into an issue, he attests, is the point at which we attempt to claim that God is emphatically comparable to an individual.5 On the off chance that God is anything like an individual, and can be judged by human models of equity, benevolence, and empathy, then he can't be all great. In this sense, the customary form of the issue of fiendishness introduces a genuine issue for the exact theist seeing that the observational theist puts stock in a humanized God.

The real concern of Hume with the problem of evil, be that as it may, is somewhat not the same as this conventional concern about compromise.

Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(The Humean Problem of Evil Coursework Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 3500 words, n.d.)
The Humean Problem of Evil Coursework Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 3500 words. https://studentshare.org/philosophy/2068336-3300-words-on-the-problem-with-evil-evil-within-religion
(The Humean Problem of Evil Coursework Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 3500 Words)
The Humean Problem of Evil Coursework Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 3500 Words. https://studentshare.org/philosophy/2068336-3300-words-on-the-problem-with-evil-evil-within-religion.
“The Humean Problem of Evil Coursework Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 3500 Words”. https://studentshare.org/philosophy/2068336-3300-words-on-the-problem-with-evil-evil-within-religion.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF The Humean Problem of Evil

The Final Stand of Evil

The following paper discusses different forms of evil existing in society and ways by which it can be put to an end.... The paper tells that the modern society has observed coexistence of evil and goodness.... With a number of flaws existing in the nature itself, the notion of evil cannot be put to an end and at the same time cannot be ignored.... Theology of modern society has always claimed the coexistence of good and evil and also raises questions regarding the final responsibility of evil....
20 Pages (5000 words) Essay

Problem of Evil and Personal Beliefs Concerning God

Name Professor Course Date problem of evil The main purpose of this paper is to demonstrate two arguments relating to the problem of evil.... The paper will first discuss the arguments from the problem of evil.... The Logical Argument Logical problem consists in the consideration that the existence of evil human beings experience questions the existence of the perfect God (Michael 320).... The Evidential Argument The evidential argument supports the fact there is some known evidence of evil that truly indicates that God does not exist (Rowe & Nick 163)....
4 Pages (1000 words) Essay

The Problem of Evil

This essay "The problem of evil" establishes a discussion of the topic through a description, analysis, and evaluation of arguments by various philosophers, and it will also establish the stance of the paper concerning the topic.... The problem of evil has caused a significant objection to the conviction regarding God's existence.... Furthermore, his approach to the problem of evil is based on the discount of the conventional perception of theodicy that is considered a justification or rationalization of evil along with suffering inflicted on people....
7 Pages (1750 words) Essay

The Problem of Sins And Evil

The first act of evil was demonstrated by Satan who due to jealously became a fallen angel.... A writer of an essay "The problem of Sins And Evil" discusses that God created the earth without sin and evil.... When I mention the word 'evil' ideas such as bad, harmful, malicious acts which result in harm and sin, negative thoughts which can be characterized by cruelty, unjust and selfish comes to my mind.... evil is the negative powerful force utilized in the battle against the positive good....
7 Pages (1750 words) Essay

The Central Problem of Philosophy of Religion

Inwagen condemns the normal taxonomy regarding the problem of evil and provides a substitute all of which are important (Łukasiewicz 448-450).... Therefore, even the ideal moral judge like God has to draw arbitrary line even when deciding on the number of evil things he would allow; therefore, the vague line guarantees that some evils in the world are gratuitous (Sullivan 398-402).... However, Inwagen insists it is unlikely that God exists given the extent as well as the degree of evil observed; hence, he notes that logical as well as evidential distinction are only but relics of history....
8 Pages (2000 words) Essay

The Problem of Evil

This essay discusses the problem of evil.... Theodicy deals with the problem of evil and attempts to explain that it is possible to assert the supremacy of God and the certainty of evil.... Philosophers have given different interpretations of the concept of evil.... All humans have the tendency to disembark on the path of evil; what prevents a particular individual from doing so, is his wisdom that he gains from his virtues and the knowledge he derives from moral values....
8 Pages (2000 words) Essay

The Problem of Evil

However, to extend the problem with this logic, it is good to look at Nelson Pike's paper on Hume on Evil as discussed by Terence Penelhum in his writing, Divine Goodness and the problem of evil.... And also the author looks at the impact of existence on the development of the supremacy, and the triumphs that good can attain in the presence of evil.... Mackie looks at the contradictions that are proposed by the existence of evil.... His treatise speaks to the logical reasoning that questions why God would allow evil if He is good, and if He is omnipotent, why does He not use that power to change the universe to a place free of evil....
12 Pages (3000 words) Term Paper

The Problem of Evil

The essay "The problem of evil" focuses on the critical analysis of the problem of evil from both logical and evidential perspectives.... The problem of evil has been long debated owing to the confusion over the existence of God, the embodiment of perfect goodness.... With a quick look at the background of the problem of evil, one finds orthodox theism blurring the logical and evidential clarity of the situation.... But the pieces of evidence of good are often overpowered by evidence of evil leading many to believe that evil arises from a source equally strong to God and worthy of worship by followers of evil (Conway, 44)....
5 Pages (1250 words) Essay
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us