Our website is a unique platform where students can share their papers in a matter of giving an example of the work to be done. If you find papers
matching your topic, you may use them only as an example of work. This is 100% legal. You may not submit downloaded papers as your own, that is cheating. Also you
should remember, that this work was alredy submitted once by a student who originally wrote it.
The paper "Kants Account of the Sublime" states that although the division between mathematical and dynamical sublimes is not without its challenges, it provides a distinctive look at how we might integrate other, non-traditional forms of sensation and think into aesthetic philosophy. …
Download full paperFile format: .doc, available for editing
Certainly every person has at least one time in his or her lifetime experienced the feeling of being overwhelmed. This aesthetic experience may come about from man’s creation or the splendours of the natural world. Regardless, all people have at sometime known what it is like to be overpowered by a breathtaking force. Of course, what a person finds overwhelming about some phenomenon is strongly dependent on its context. For instance, a 16th century merchant would see any obsolete 20th-century piece of technology as an extraordinary achievement of mankind. Nevertheless, although the objects that bear these aesthetic properties change through time and space, the feeling itself remains constant in terms of how it is experienced and when it is experienced. This notion of being overwhelmed by a property of greatness has been floated around in philosophy for millennia, and only really came to widespread attention with the writings of Immanuel Kant on aesthetics. Kant came to identify what he called the sublime (or, in German, Erhabenen) as something quite different from the concept of beautiful. Beautiful, for Kant, can only be found in objects that are bounded insofar as beauty is “connected with the form of the object” (191). Obviously, for some object to have form, it must have some semblance of an edge. The sublime, however, pertains to something quite different: something without bounds and something that is dynamical in nature.
The sublime refers, of course, to those experiences that we cannot describe as “beautiful”. For instance, we cannot call a violent storm, or a brilliant mathematical equation, or a complex piece of equipment “beautiful”. These things may overwhelm us, but it would strictly be a categorical error to ascribe the same aesthetic qualities to them that we might ascribe to a beautiful painting or a beautiful sculpture. Storms, equations, and technology serve separate functions besides helping us appreciate beautiful things. It is the extent to which the former items serve their different functions that overwhelms us. A violent storm, for instance, fulfils the “function” (with that word being used loosely) of destroying things far more effective than a weak storm, and thus the violent storm is more sublime than the weaker one.
Kant cleverly separated the sublime into dynamical and mathematical. The former of which refers to a situation in which, metaphysically, our wills are resisted by the sheer force of the event, such as in the case of the storm. The latter of which refers to a situation in which, epistemologically, full understanding of the situation is practically impossible, such as in the case of the mathematical equation and its applications to the real world. Epistemologically, the sublime is of such a great magnitude that it requires entirely different concepts, and must be (as a necessary condition) of a great magnitude. Metaphysically, Kant says, “nature considered in an aesthetic judgment as might that has no dominion over us, is dynamically sublime” (260). In other words, the sublime considered dynamically expresses some kind of force over the subject, emergent from the aesthetic object in question.
We might thus wonder what it means, based on these dynamical and mathematical interpretations of the sublime, to be “formless” as Kant believes the sublime to be. The mathematical sublime, as has been said, is large beyond all comparison and is thereby absolutely large. Any finite object in the universe capable of being perceived is therefore measurable, such as a storm or a mountain. Nevertheless, for Kant, measurement is not merely a matter of quantitative values assigned according to some standard: it relies more fundamentally on an understanding of what a unit of such a measurement is. Indeed, a number is a necessary but not sufficient condition of measurement. A unit satisfies that sufficient condition. Thus, because a human being’s faculties are limited, the measurement of any object will be finite. We impose limits both on numbers and units for epistemological reasons, and any object that may proceed to exceed these artificial limitations, based on what is inherent to the human mind’s ability to understand, will be thought of in Kant’s terms as large beyond all comparison. What this means in reality, however, remains less than clear.
With these considerations of the sublime out of the way, there remains something else troubling the Kantian picture of the aesthetic. The question of where the sublime fits within Kant’s aesthetic teleology remains unanswered. Kant spoke of pleasure teleologically, as the achievement of an end. On the other hand, Kant often refers to the sublime as “contrapurposive”: “We see from this at once that we express ourselves entirely incorrectly when we call this or that object of nature sublime, even though we may quite correctly call a great many natural objects beautiful; for how can we call something by a term of approval if we apprehend it as in itself contrapurposive?” (245). This problem, for Kant, directs toward a reconceptualization of what is actually going on when we describe something as sublime in the sense that it is of a fantastic magnitude. The sublime, instead of just being this mere awesomeness, must lie deeper in the issue of epistemology.
Kant then reformulates the concept of the sublime by taking the focus off of the object of our perception: the storms, the mountains, the equations, the technology, and toward our own ideas. The awesomeness of such sensible objects—objects that enter our minds and with such great magnitudes in size or importance—overwhelms us to create the idea of a truly awe-inspiring object. Our faculty of reason, which plays such a crucial role in the whole of Kantianism, insists on being offered such sights and sounds. Although the sublime is at one level contrapurposive, it is at another something that our higher faculties (beyond the mere sensible displeasure of being overwhelmed) demands of us. At this higher level, it is purposive insofar as it is what Kant calls a “negative pleasure” (245). Although the sublime consists of both of these seemingly contradictory aspects, it still remains an “alteration” between these two feelings.
Kant’s account of the sublime, as it is traditionally interpreted anyway, raises many questions as to whether the concept is indeed valid or not. We are left with a substantial difficulty actually differentiating the dynamic from the mathematical sublime. Kant gives the account summarized here of how rational beings use the concepts of number and unit in conjunction to approximate the mathematical sublime, but leaves the reader without one on the corollary “force” as it pertains to our concept of the dynamic sublime. It seems as though the criterion he sets down for magnitude in the mathematical sense are supposed to carry over for the dynamic sense and its “force”. However, the supposed difference between magnitude and force does not permit us to do so and thus the distinction seems to be in peril. This occurs because of Kant’s attempts to fit the sublime in the teleological aesthetic, and the extraction of the sublime from a mere matter of being overwhelmed to a rational comparison of two possibilities. The sublime, taken as an alternating between two epistemologies (the lower-level displeasure of being overwhelmed and the higher-level pleasure of being overwhelmed), removes the metaphysical aspect of the sublime and constricts it to how it affects our rational faculties.
Kant’s sublime is truly an interesting contribution to the field of aesthetics, and reintroduces a concept that may be useful in describing a very unique phenomenon. Although the division between mathematical and dynamical sublimes is not without its challenges, it provides a distinctive look at how we might integrate other, non-traditional forms of sensation and thinking into aesthetic philosophy. Crowther (1991) says that the sublime also has an integral place not only in Kantian aesthetic philosophy, but in the context of his ethical system, which places an enormous value on human freedom . Kant extracts the sublime from nature by making it a matter of comparison between two possibilities. Being able not to grasp a sublime phenomenon, for Kant, provides a criterion of evaluating the differing sensibilities of human beings, and their potential for moral action.
Works Cited
Crowther, P. (1991). The Kantian Sublime: From Morality to Art. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kant, I. (1987). Critique of Judgment. New York: Hackett Publishing Company.
Read
More
Share:
CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF Kants Account of the Sublime
Name: Instructor: Institution: Date: An analytical view of Constable's landscape paintings in comparison to Turner and Friedrich John Constable was an unsurpassed artist of tranquil countryside England, who focused particularly on his resident countryside of Suffolk.... ... ... ... The brilliant, clear ambiance of Constable's works distinguishes penetratingly from the cumbersome ambience of Turner....
This “something that can be conceived but not seen nor made visible” is often referred to as the sublime, a quality of transcendent greatness “with which nothing else can be compared and which is beyond all possibility of calculation, measurement or imitation” (Wikipedia, 2006).... The presence of this sublime element, then, inspires the imagination in a specific direction based on which elements remain visible or understandable.... It is associated in this account with those who “pursue successful careers in mass conformism by communicating by means of the ‘correct rules,' the endemic desire for reality with objects and situations capable of gratifying it” (Lyotard, 1979, p....
More so, homeownership is “a forced saving device”1 allowing borrowers to access the equity in their homes.... However, to achieve that “American.... ... ... As such, for many Americans the means to achieving the “American Dream” or tapping the equity in their home is through the option of a subprime mortgage....
They both do so with the aid of monumental support from the literature throughout the entire history of philosophy, moving from Plato to.... ... ... Although both authors introduce a vast scope of input from such a history, the focus here will be on Kant particularly, and his notions of the aesthetic....
This paper ''Human Status in Regards to Aristotle and Kant'' tells that The problem of a person is one of central in the history of philosophy.... It was realized and became a reflection subject already in antique Greece.... Today in the XXI century, when the rich knowledge of a person has been already accumulated....
Find a recent (September 2015-Dec.... 2015) money and banking related article in the media (the Economist, Globe and Mail, National Post, New York Times, etc.... ), and attempt to explain parts or all of it using the tools we learned in class.... ... ... ... The article gives its opinion about the global monetary system by discussing how America is likely to be at the center of this global financial system....
The paper "Picturesque as the Limits of Beautiful and Sublime" investigates the account of the three expressions as they speak about British as well as American scenery painting.... It depicts paintings within the beautiful practice as containing tranquil.... ... ... ... It is significant to make a note of the expression balanced in this depiction, as it brings to mind the idea of the beautiful....
This paper "Kants Discussion of the sublime Assessment" discusses the relations between sublime and beauty, the idea of Kant on sublime, the two concepts of beauty, and sublime comparing to the sublime as an independent concept, major similarities existing between the sublime and the beauty.... The relations between sublime and beauty are also established before looking at the various methods by which the sublime may be identified.... Even though the sublime is commonly defined and described from the basis of qualities including something that is elevated, lofty, and exalted, Kant viewed the sublime to encompass the characters of grandeur rather than loftiness (Rueger & Evren, 2005)....
12 Pages(3000 words)Essay
sponsored ads
Save Your Time for More Important Things
Let us write or edit the essay on your topic
"Kants Account of the Sublime"
with a personal 20% discount.