StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

Governmental Interference - Term Paper Example

Cite this document
Summary
In this paper, the author demonstrated how the involvement of the government in some specific aspect of the lives of its citizens does not violate their individual liberty. Also, the author drew between private and social concerns and legislation that attempts to promote good conduct…
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER97.5% of users find it useful
Governmental Interference
Read Text Preview

Extract of sample "Governmental Interference"

Does doing the right thing ever lead to worse overall circumstances than doing the wrong thing? At the outset of the nineteenth century, an influential group of British thinkers developed a set of basic principles for addressing social problems. Extrapolating from Humes emphasis on the natural human interest in utility, reformer Jeremy Bentham proposed a straightforward quantification of morality by reference to utilitarian outcomes. His An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (1789) offers a simple statement of the application of this ethical doctrine. Benthams moral theory was founded on the assumption that it is the consequences of human actions that count in evaluating their merit and that the kind of consequence that matters for human happiness is just the achievement of pleasure and avoidance of pain. He argued that the hedonistic value of any human action is easily calculated by considering how intensely its pleasure is felt, how long that pleasure lasts, how certainly and how quickly it follows upon the performance of the action, and how likely it is to produce collateral benefits and avoid collateral harms. Taking such matters into account, we arrive at a net value of each action for any human being affected by it. All that remains, Bentham supposed, is to consider the extent of this pleasure, since the happiness of the community as a whole is nothing other than the sum of individual human interests. The principle of utility, then, defines the meaning of moral obligation by reference to the greatest happiness of the greatest number of people who are affected by performance of an action. Similarly, Bentham supposed that social policies are properly evaluated in light of their effect on the general well-being of the populations they involve. Punishing criminals is an effective way of deterring crime precisely because it pointedly alters the likely outcome of their actions, attaching the likelihood of future pain in order to outweigh the apparent gain of committing the crime. Thus, punishment must "fit" the crime by changing the likely perception of the value of committing it. A generation later, utilitarianism found its most effective exponent in John Stuart Mill. Raised by his father, the philosopher James Mill, on strictly Benthamite principles, Mill devoted his life to the defence and promotion of the general welfare. With the help his long-time companion Harriet Taylor, Mill became a powerful champion of lofty moral and social ideals. Mills Utilitarianism (1861) is an extended explanation of utilitarian moral theory. In an effort to respond to criticisms of the doctrine, Mill not only argued in favor of the basic principles of Jeremy Bentham but also offered several significant improvements to its structure, meaning, and application. Although the progress of moral philosophy has been limited by its endless disputes over the reality and nature of the highest good, Mill assumed from the outset, everyone can agree that the consequences of human actions contribute importantly to their moral value. (Utilitarianism 1) Mill fully accepted Benthams devotion to greatest happiness principle as the basic statement of utilitarian value: " . . . actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure." (Utilitarianism 2) But he did not agree that all differences among pleasures can be quantified. On Mills view, some kinds of pleasure experienced by human beings also differ from each other in qualitative ways, and only those who have experienced pleasure of both sorts are competent judges of their relative quality. This establishes the moral worth of promoting higher (largely intellectual) pleasures among sentient beings even when their momentary intensity may be less than that of alternative lower (largely bodily) pleasures. Even so, Mill granted that the positive achievement of happiness is often difficult, so that we are often justified morally in seeking primarily to reduce the total amount of pain experienced by sentient beings affected by our actions. Pain—or even the sacrifice of pleasure—is warranted on Mills view only when it results directly in the greater good of all. Against those who argue that the utilitarian theory unreasonably demands of individual agents that they devote their primary energies to the cold-hearted and interminable calculation of anticipated effects of their actions, Mill offered a significant qualification. Precisely because we do not have the time to calculate accurately in every instance, he supposed, we properly allow our actions to be guided by moral rules most of the time. Partly anticipating the later distinction between act and rule utilitarianism, Mill pointed out that secondary moral principles at the very least perform an important service by providing ample guidance for every-day moral life. Finally, however, he emphasized that the value of each particular action—especially in difficult or controversial cases—is to be determined by reference to the principle of utility itself. What motivates people to do the right thing? Mill claimed universal agreement on the role of moral sanctions in eliciting proper conduct from human agents. (Utilitarianism 3) But unlike Bentham, Mill did not restrict himself to the socially-imposed external sanctions of punishment and blame, which make the consequences of improper action more obviously painful. On Mills view, human beings are also motivated by such internal sanctions as self-esteem, guilt, and conscience. Because we all have social feelings on behalf of others, the unselfish wish for the good of all is often enough to move us to act morally. Even if others do not blame or punish me for doing wrong, I am likely to blame myself, and that bad feeling is another of the consequent pains that I reasonably consider when deciding what to do. In Chapter Four, Mill offers as "proof" of the principle of utility an argument originally presented by his father, James Mill. The best evidence of the desirability of happiness is that people really do desire it; and since each individual human being desires her own happiness, it must follow that all of us desire the happiness of everyone. Thus, the Mills argued, the greatest pleasure of all is morally desirable. (Utilitarianism 4) The argument doesnt hold up well at all in logical terms, since each of its inferences is obviously fallacious, but Mill may have been correct in supposing on psychological grounds that seeking pleasure and avoiding pain are the touchstones by which most of us typically live. Finally, Mill argued that social applications of the principle of utility are fully consistent with traditional concern for the promotion of justice. Justice involves respect for the property, rights, and deserts of individual citizens, along with fundamental presumptions in favor of good faith and impartiality. All of these worthwhile components of justice are adequately preserved by conscientious application of the principle of utility, Mill supposed, since particular cases of each clearly result in the greatest happiness of all affected parties. (Utilitarianism 5) Although a retributive sentiment in favor of punishing wrong-doers may also be supposed to contribute to the traditional concept of justice, Mill insisted that the appropriately limited use of external sanctions on utilitarian grounds better accords with a legitimate respect for the general welfare. Mill also pointed out that the defence of individual human freedom is especially vital to living justly, but that had been the subject of another book. John Stuart Mills On Liberty (1859) is the classic statement and defence of the view that governmental encroachment upon the freedom of individuals is almost never warranted. A genuinely civil society, he maintained, must always guarantee the civil liberty of its citizens—their protection against interference by an abusive authority. This is true even when the government itself relies upon the democratic participation of the people. (On Liberty 1) The tyranny of the majority is especially dangerous to individual liberty, Mill supposed, because the most commonly recommended remedy is to demand that the recalcitrant minority either persuade the majority to change its views or learn to conform to socially accepted norms. Mill had a different notion. The proper balance between individual liberty and governmental authority, he proposed, can be stated as a simple principle: "[T]he only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others." (On Liberty 1) Although society has a clear responsibility for protecting its citizens from each other, it has no business interfering with the rest of what they do. In particular, anything that directly affects only the individual citizen must remain absolutely free. On Mills view, this entails in particular that the government is never justified in trying to control, limit, or restrain: 1) private thoughts and feelings, along with their public expression, 2) individual tastes and pursuits as efforts to live happily, or 3) the association of like-minded individuals with each other. (On Liberty 1) No society is truly free unless its individual citizens are permitted to take care of themselves. Considering first freedom of thought and discussion, Mill argued that because even a majority opinion is fallible, society should always permit the expression of minority views. There is a chance, after all, that the unconventional opinion will turn out, in the long run, to be correct, in which case the entire society would suffer if it were never allowed to come to light. Sincere devotion to the truth requires open inquiry, not the purposeful silencing of alternative views that might prove to be right. (On Liberty 2) Even if the unconventional opinion turns out to be incorrect, Mill argued, there is still good reason to encourage its free expression. The truth can only be enlivened and strengthened by exposure to criticism and debate through which the majority view is shown not to be merely an inadequately grounded superstition. (On Liberty 2) In the most common instance, Mill supposed, there will actually turn out to be some measure of falsity in the clearest truth and some element of truth in the most patent falsehood. Thus, on every possible occasion, encouraging civil discussion of alternative views genuinely benefits society as a whole. Mill supposed that behavior as well as thought often deserves protection against social encroachment. Human action should arise freely from the character of individual human beings, not from the despotic influence of public opinion, custom, or expectation. No matter what patterns of behavior may constitute the way we ought to be, he argued, each person must choose her or his own path in life, even if it differs significantly from what other people would recommend. (On Liberty 3) No less than in the realm of thought, in the realm of behavior unconventionality and originality are often signs of great personal genius, which should never be curtailed by social pressures. In summary, then, Mill emphasized that individual citizens are responsible for themselves, their thoughts and feelings, and their own tastes and pursuits, while society is properly concerned only with social interests. In particular, the state is justified in limiting or controlling the conduct of individuals only when doing so is the only way to prevent them from doing harm to others by violating their rights. (On Liberty 4) Where the conduct in question affects only the person who does it—even if it clearly results in harm to that person—the state has no business in even trying to suppress the mode of being that person has chosen. Thus, on Mills view, legislation that attempts to promote good conduct or to prevent people from harming themselves is always wrong. The line he drew between private and social concerns is a fairly clear one: society should not endeavor to limit my drinking, but rightly prosecutes me for harming others while drunk. In the essays final chapter, Mill carefully noted several apparent exceptions to the general principle. (On Liberty 5) Governmental interference is not necessary even in some of the instances where it might be justifiable. Economic life involves social interest and may therefore be subject to regulation, even though free trade is often more effective. Speech or action by one individual that encourages someone else to commit self-harm is appropriately restricted. Indirect action by the state designed to encourage or discourage (without requiring or restraining) individual conduct is permissible; in fact, doing so is simply good utilitarian legislation. According to Mill, the states legitimate interest in preventing harm to its citizens extends even into the domain of family life, as in forbidding spousal abuse or providing for the education of children. Finally, Mill noted that even if the involvement of the government in some specific aspect of the lives of its citizens does not violate their individual liberty, there may remain other good reasons for avoiding it. If the conduct to be regulated can be performed better by individuals themselves, if it is more desirable that it be done by them, or if regulation would add significantly to the already-dangerous power of the social establishment, then the state ought not to be allowed to interfere. (On Liberty 5) Mills conclusion, then, is strictly in favor of liberty: governmental action is legitimate only when demonstrably necessary for the protection of other citizens from direct harm caused by the conduct in question. On every other contingency, the liberty of the individual should remain inviolate. Bibliography Primary sources: The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill (Toronto, 1963- ) John Stuart Mill, Autobiography, ed. by John Robson (Penguin, 1990) John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism and Other Essays, ed. by Alan Ryan (Viking, 1987) John Stuart Mill, On Liberty and Utilitarianism (Bantam, 1993) John Stuart Mill, The Subjection of Women (Prometheus, 1986) John Stuart Mill, Principles of Political Economy: And Chapters on Socialism, ed. by Jonathan Riley (Oxford, 1999) Secondary sources: Mills on Liberty: Critical Essays, ed. by Gerald Dworkin (Rowman & Littlefield, 1997) The Cambridge Companion to Mill, ed. by John Skorupski (Cambridge, 1997) Roger Crisp, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Mill on Utilitarianism (Routledge, 1997) Jonathan Riley, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Mill on Liberty (Routledge, 1998) An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (1789) A Fragment on Government (1776) Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(Governmental Interference Term Paper Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 2250 words, n.d.)
Governmental Interference Term Paper Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 2250 words. Retrieved from https://studentshare.org/law/1703711-see-below
(Governmental Interference Term Paper Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 2250 Words)
Governmental Interference Term Paper Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 2250 Words. https://studentshare.org/law/1703711-see-below.
“Governmental Interference Term Paper Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 2250 Words”, n.d. https://studentshare.org/law/1703711-see-below.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF Governmental Interference

Marketing Plan for Canadian Blood Services

Canadian Blood Service Case Analysis Institution Date Memo Canadian Blood Services Case Analysis Date: To: From: Subject: Draft Marketing Plan for Canadian Blood Services Following your concern and request, the following is a draft strategy aimed at increasing donor numbers as well as repeat donations with the ultimate objective of increasing your blood supply....
4 Pages (1000 words) Research Paper

What Are The Concepts Upon Which Laissez Faire Is Based

The French phrase even found place in England later in the 18th century with respect to protests for bringing about free trade and non-interference or non-intervention by the government.... At the time, there were pioneer economists in France who were known as the Physiocrats, and they led to the primary development of the theory of laissez-faire, which emphasized on non-interference with commercial ventures in order to protect the interests of those yearning to set up their own empires....
4 Pages (1000 words) Essay

How the United Nations help people around the world

It, thus, provides an avenue to the aggrieved parties, through the international law courts, to be heard fairly without the respective Governmental Interference.... Founded in 1945, the United Nations came into existence as a replacement to the defunct League of Nations; an organization that had literally failed to reign in rogue governments leading to a bloody repeat of a world war,only two decades after a first....
3 Pages (750 words) Essay

Main principles of industrial revolution

The popular method of illuminating the Industrial Revolution is to enumerate a list of factors that paved the way for its development.... (More 158) Such an approach usually includes items like growing demand due to population increase, growth of export, changes in taste, capital availability, scientific knowledge and the skill of the artisans....
3 Pages (750 words) Essay

Censorship and Shock Jocks

1 Without profanity, however, it could be argued that the FCC's challenges to these various radio talk show hosts are ruining artists' output. Howard Stern has said, "It is pretty shocking that Governmental Interference into our rights and free speech takes place in the U.... What constitutes entertainment to some people can be a tempest in a teapot....
4 Pages (1000 words) Essay

Two Mercantilist Movement Reformers and Critics

Francois… y as a member of the Physiocrat movement is such a critic of the mercantilist movement, arguing for a natural order to economic activities that are governed by natural laws, rather than human and Governmental Interference.... Francois Quesney as a member of the Physiocrat movement is such a critic of the mercantilist movement, arguing for a natural order to economic activities that are governed by natural laws, rather than human and Governmental Interference....
1 Pages (250 words) Assignment

Global issues

The process of globalization sparked for the first time in more than a century ago, and gained momentum in the late 20th century, turning the world… The position of Von Hayek unfolded in the documentary is based on the belief that Governmental Interference and control of the market isn't needed.... he position of Von Hayek unfolded in the documentary is based on the belief that Governmental Interference and control of the market isn't needed.... eynes' purpose, to the contrary, was to subject economy to the governmental central planning....
1 Pages (250 words) Assignment

Environmental Ethics

The paper "Environmental Ethics" discusses the dilemma people confront - the spreading out of the social conscience from individuals to nature or land.... nbsp;No significant adjustment in ethics was ever achieved without an intrinsic modification in people's intellectual focus, dedications, and convictions....
5 Pages (1250 words) Essay
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us