Our website is a unique platform where students can share their papers in a matter of giving an example of the work to be done. If you find papers
matching your topic, you may use them only as an example of work. This is 100% legal. You may not submit downloaded papers as your own, that is cheating. Also you
should remember, that this work was alredy submitted once by a student who originally wrote it.
From the paper "The Concept of Virtue" it is clear that factors of life are extremely difficult to capture, especially in an objective sense. Perhaps this is an advantage, but it can lead to incomplete accounts; the Stoics do not exactly define what is meant by will in accordance with nature…
Download full paperFile format: .doc, available for editing
The concept of virtue is surrounded by factors concerning human reason, and the particular theme of the soul. The main areas of distinction between theories appear to be based on the nature of virtue as a state and as an activity. Furthermore, general differences also include whether there exists a fundamental, underlying concept of virtue or whether a list of specific virtuous elements is possible. Of course, such theoretical discourse is bound to result in differentiating theories; the inspiration behind assessing the concept of human virtue is abound with rich possibilities and profound considerations.
Aristotle’s account of human virtue is somewhat unique. For Aristotle, man’s function is the rational part of the soul acting in accordance with virtue (1097b22-1098a20). ‘In the view of the active people at least, virtue is superior’ (1095b30) and causes us to seek some form(s) of good. Thus Aristotle’s approach is distinctly a search for good, though not of listed goods. Rather, he searches for the most desirable good - the Highest Good, which is desirable for itself rather than for the sake of some other good: ‘The good is spoken of both in what-it-is and in quality and relative; and what is in itself’ (1096a20;12). This Highest Good is the attainment of happiness and wellbeing, which causes other goals to be sought inasmuch as they promote wellbeing rather than consisting of wellbeing per se. We have the capacity to live a better life by guiding ourselves through the use of reason and thus living in happiness. But because good has so many forms, it cannot be a single universal formation, ‘for if it were, it would be spoken of only in one of the predications, not in them all’ (1096a25;6-7). We need other forms of good as well, he acknowledges, such as friends and power; happiness is delicate if we lack severely some advantage (1099a31-b6).
Although this severe lack may need some good fortune to allow occurrences to chance in our favor, Aristotle asserts that virtuous activity does not itself come to us by chance. We have the responsibility for employing and possessing the virtues and we are all born with the potential to have virtue; it is ‘the soul’s activity that expresses reason’ (1098a5-6). We must first develop proper habits, and secondly, acquire practical wisdom once our reason has become fully developed. When combined with practical reason, this virtue becomes fully developed.
Aristotle explains happiness not as a virtue, but as virtuous activity; living well requires action rather than state. Evil people are solely driven by desire for luxury; they may never satisfy their desire and will not reach happiness. Thus, for Aristotle, happiness is not the fulfillment of desire; it is a balance maintained between excess and deficiency, in the subjective sense (1106a26-b28). Virtue is the tendency to have appropriate feelings (1105b25-6) and involves emotional responses rather than intellectual conditions (thus it is different from knowledge). There is no universal mean for every man, recognizes Aristotle; rather, it should never undermine reason, and each individual finds their mean point through reason ‘in the way that the person of practical reason would determine it’ (1107a7-2).
Socrates, quite like Aristotle, searches for the deeper quality of virtuous behavior: ‘even if they are many and various, all of them have one and the same form which makes them virtues’ (72c4-7). He acknowledges that we desire good things, but because we may not know what is evil, good must be ‘accompanied by justice or moderation…or some other part of virtue; if it is not, it will not be virtue’ (78d8-e2). Socrates searches for virtue in its whole form, rather than Meno’s part-definitions. Rather we are all good ‘in the same way’ (73c1-2) because we acquire the same qualities in order to become good.
Again, like Aristotle, Socrates believes that virtue is within the soul, and because it is immortal, it has knowledge within it already – we must recollect this knowledge through questions (81c4). Thus virtue cannot be taught; it is already within us and not dependent on factors such as gender or age (73b). Again, he brings one back to the single meaning of virtue; to simply list various types of virtue is to make many out of one (77a). For all of his reasoning and deliberation, Socrates does not seem to actually arrive at a single definition of virtue. He favors self-development over materialistic desires and truly good action rather than that which is believed to be good. The most final of his statements is as thus: ‘virtue is neither natural nor acquired, but an instinct given by God to the virtuous’ (99e4).
The Stoics’ main belief is that human virtue maintains a will in accord with nature, which ‘enables man to achieve this [goal] in its own way’ (John Stobaeus: Anthology 5b3;2). Because all men are seen as equal sons of God, everything good or bad in life depends on man himself. We all have perfect freedom if we can avoid ‘everything which either is vice or participates in vice’ (John Stobaeus: Anthology 5a;6) and understand that health, happiness and possessions have no value. Fundamentally, a life in harmony with the universe is promoted as virtue by the stoics; but over which we have no direct control: ‘what is necessitated is no different from what is fated’ (Theodoretus: Graecarum Affectionum Cura 6.14;1-2). The good resides within the soul, through wisdom and self-control we can achieve freedom from suffering by attaining a ‘good blend of the beliefs in the soul’ (John Stobaeus: Anthology 5b4;7).
For the Stoics, to live in virtue is to live in harmony with nature; to understand the order of the universe rather than ‘confidence and wish’ (John Stobaeus: Anthology, 5b;3-4). Unlike Aristotle, the Stoics list the four cardinal virtues: wisdom, courage, justice and temperance (John Stobaeus: Anthology, 5b2); each is a type of knowledge. To come back into the reason of nature and move into harmony with it removes the evil seen as a result of ignorance and allows the virtuous qualities to remain within: ‘natural ability in the soul is more helpful for virtue than natural ability in the body’ John Stobaeus: Anthology, 7b;27).
The three accounts of virtue are not profoundly distinct from one another; indeed there are some fundamental similarities that connect them. All three recount to the idea that virtue is within the soul; this indeed is a strong facet and can relate to the principle that virtue cannot be taught. Aristotle’s account is rather plausible in that it relates to the seeking of good in the form of happiness and wellbeing. Indeed, humans do seek happiness and wellbeing; this can be the basic foundation for all virtuous activity. Yet he does not seem to account for the fact that one may be virtuous and inactive – one could argue that the very essence of virtuous happiness is not actively seeking it further. All three also establish that the desire for luxury and material goods is not virtuous; this is highly plausible as ones desire in this sense does tend to be insatiable.
The very fact that Socrates does not formally establish a final definition of virtue is can be rather attractive. In this sense, he may be acknowledging that virtue is not actually definable, rather it is an element that can only be described. Indeed, to state virtue as a specific factor, such as temperance or patience, confines it unnecessarily. It could be argued that virtue can be found everywhere; to specifically define it may remove its potential to inspire. In this sense, Socrates, by resisting defining virtue per se, is appealing to its universality; its diversity and indeed its very essence. Perhaps, by trying to specifically define virtue, one may stunt its actual qualities. On the other hand, the Stoics, by listing the four cardinal virtues, allow one to grasp on a more specific level its actuality. Often to consider such an issue can result in remote concepts; by capturing it on a more concrete level, the Stoics have created a more plausible theory of virtue. Generally, such factors of life are extremely difficult to capture, especially in an objective sense. Perhaps this is an advantage, but it can lead to incomplete accounts; the Stoics do not exactly define what is meant by will in accordance with nature.
Read
More
He brought up the issue on the meaning of The Concept of Virtue to present himself as a person who has the knowledge about virtue.... The discussion regarding virtue can be considered beneficial to Socrates because through the dialogue, he was able to present himself as a person who knows the meaning of The Concept of Virtue.... The said discussion on the other hand is significant to the readers as a trigger towards a deeper view on the general concept of virtue, which is important since the meaning of the word itself is often overlooked....
Virtue according to Plato can only be observed in philosophers or people of knowledge since they are aware of The Concept of Virtue itself.... The view on virtue is also another example.... Through the dialogue of Phaedo, Plato had been able to present one of his greatest contributions to philosophy which is the perspective of dualities, wherein every concept is viewed and given reason through the opposing concept.... He again related another concept to knowledge....
The paper "The Concept of Virtue Ethics" suggests that ethics includes the required acts or non-acts in any given situation.... The study will scrutinize virtue ethics.... virtue ethics focuses on implementing what is morally right.... According to Immanuel Kant, justice virtue is included in his famous metaphysics of morals.... The justice virtue ethics can be applied to each sweatshop operation.... Second, another virtue is fairness....
he author speaks of Nous, or the ability to reason, as the cause of virtue, and he divides people in four groups accordingly: the Virtuous (enjoy doing what's right and do so without any moral dilemma); the Continent (do virtuous things most of the time, but must overcome conflict); the Incontinent (faced with the same moral conflict, usually choose against virtue), and the Vicious (see little value or interest in Virtue, and do not attempt it, at all).... While the former is concerned with obeying laws, and the relation of virtue to others, the latter deals with unjust profits from action, and divides in the distribution of visible goods, and the rectification in transactions....
This essay "Virtue in Philosophy of Machiavelli" focuses on estimating Machiavelli's conception of virtue is undeniably difficult with obscurity, especially in the context of two different types of works, namely The Prince and the Discourses.... nd, this is what is objectionable in The Prince where he goes against the morality set by the classical and biblical values with an intention of framing a novel and modern "political" conception of virtue.... The new definition of virtue means something that does not prevent the human from first gaining and then maintaining whatever has been gained, especially the authority....
virtue ethics reasoning A form of ethical theory that makes The Concept of Virtue and virtuous action its primary or fundamental concepts.... Different approaches to ethical concerns come from the perspective of virtue ethics, normative ethics, personal ethics and/or professional ethics.... The decision can be justified using virtue ethics as well.... While most prevailing ethical theories make either the principle of the good or the principle of the right fundamental, virtue ethics gives these principles only a derivative status....
The Concept of Virtue ethics originated from the philosophers of Plato and Aristotle.... the concept of amoral is when one won't make a judgment based on the moral distinction with a lack of sensibility toward right or wrong.... the concept of morality is relative.... The paper "Values and Morality of a Human" discusses that virtue ethics implies that one should act according to the belief that is held and what one sees as virtuous....
In contemporary society, The Concept of Virtue or ethics starts with the basic assumptions that all employee live in accordance with the moral guidelines.... Confucius and Aristotle on Virtue Confucius and Aristotle on Virtue Virtue refers to behaviour that illustrates high moral standards and, therefore, the concept of moral excellence.... According to the concept of ‘virtue ethics' by Aristotle, it is challenging to attain morality in a universal code....
2 Pages(500 words)Essay
sponsored ads
Save Your Time for More Important Things
Let us write or edit the essay on your topic
"The Concept of Virtue"
with a personal 20% discount.