StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism f the Communist Party - Coursework Example

Cite this document
Summary
The paper "Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism οf the Communist Party" states that crimes committed by the bourgeoisie are crimes οf domination and repression, and are designed to keep the proletariat in place. Crimes committed by the proletariat are crimes οf accommodation or resistance to the bourgeoisie…
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER95.1% of users find it useful
Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism f the Communist Party
Read Text Preview

Extract of sample "Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism f the Communist Party"

Marxist Political Economy Introduction This historical connection οf Marxist theory with conflict theory presents an interesting paradox οf a Marxism reared in the womb οf theoretical structures to which it was, and is, seemingly largely opposed. Marxist theory has in common with conflict theory an interest in explaining both law and criminal justice but rejects the multi- group conflict image οf society and endorses a power- elite model οf society, in which social, economic, and political power has been concentrated into the hands οf a small ruling class in late-stage capitalism. The history οf 'civilized' society, for Marx, has been the history οf different forms οf class exploitation and domination. It is the form οf class domination present which determines the general character οf the whole social structure. For example, the growing οf wheat using traditional, non-mechanical techniques is compatible with a wide range οf social relations οf production. A Roman citizen often owned slaves who worked his land growing wheat; a feudal lord would seize the surplus wheat grown by the serf on the lands; the early capitalist farmers began to employ landless labourers to do their manual work for a wage that was less than the total value οf the product that they created. In each case, wheat is grown on land by the labour οf men and women, but the social arrangements are totally different. There are totally different class relationships, leading to totally different forms οf society: ancient, feudal, and capitalist. The one thing that unites these three arrangements is that in each case a minority class rules and takes the surplus away from the producers. Each society, says Marx, embodies class exploitation based on the relationships οf production, or rather, the modes οf production. The key to understanding a given society is to discover which is the dominant mode οf production within it. The basic pattern οf social and political relationships can then be known. Since Marx concentrates his attention on the class structure οf capitalist societies, it is only proper to follow him. As stated before, the key classes in the capitalist mode οf production are the bourgeoisie and the proletariat, or capitalists and landless wage labourers. While Marx recognizes that there are other classes, the fundamental class division is between this pairing οf the exploiter and the exploited. The bourgeoisie derive their class position from the fact that they own productive wealth. It is not their high income that makes them capitalists, but the fact that they own the means οf production. For example, the inputs necessary for production - factories, machines, etc. The ability οf workers to work (labour power) is in itself a marketable commodity bought for the least cost to be used at will by the capitalist. In addition, the capitalist owns the product and will always pocket the difference between the value οf the labour and the value οf the product - referred to by Marx as 'surplus value' - purely by virtue οf his ownership. His property rights also allow the capitalist the control οf the process οf production and the labour he buys. The proletariat in contrast, owns no means οf production. Because οf this exploitation, Marx viewed the bourgeoisie and the proletariat as locked in deep and unavoidable conflict. The criminal justice system, in the words or Marx, is used against, rather than for the people. Under capitalism, the system οf law and punishment is inherently unjust, designed not to control crime for the good οf the society but to subjugate the population. For instance, imprisonment is imposed less as a direct punishment for convicted felons than as a way to siphon off surplus labour from the population. Since a long cycle οf growth and depression is inherent in capitalism, there will be times when there are too many workers that the economy cannot absorb. These surplus workers are a threat to capitalists, since they could organize into a revolutionary movement. Therefore, the theory explains the imprisonment οf criminal offenders as simply another way to regulate the availability and cost οf labour. Akers argues that much οf Marxist theory is really an ideological condemnation οf Western democracies and a call for revolutionary action to overthrow them. The evidence on the theory that the criminal justice system responses to crime are affected by the political economy has been tested and proved to be mixed. Marx wrote very little about criminal behaviour, and Marxist theorists have recognized that there can be no pure Marxist theory οf crime. Marxists concentrate on criminal law and the criminal justice system. If the Marxist view οf capitalist society as criminogenic is valid, then crime should be very low, if non existent, in all socialist societies. The theory explains differences in the crime rate across types οf society, but it does not explain difference in individual or group behaviour within the same society. Therefore, any analysis οf variations in crime solely within the same society cannot test the theory. American society during the Great Depression offered no end οf stimuli to economic thought. Financial crash and industrial stagnation threw millions out οf work, growth was anemic at best until the Second World War, and the consequent conviction that Karl Marx's economic anticipations had been proven correct led unprecedented numbers οf intellectuals to embrace Marxism. Under such circumstances one might expect the American left to produce an outpouring οf economic analysis, and that, indeed, is the presupposition οf many accounts. Louis Adamic recalled "elaborate analyses and diagnoses οf the rapidly disintegrating socio-economic structure οf the United States" during the first years οf the 1930s (1938,325). "In those days," Malcolm Cowley concurred, "everyone was trying to be an economist οf sorts. Writers studied 'conditions,' as they called them, in various cities or industries and tried to publish their findings as pamphlets" (1981, 27). But what is most striking about the contours οf American economic thought in the 1930s is less the volume οf contributions from the left that one would expect to find than the paucity οf sustained Marxist crisis theory and debate. Between 1929, when a precipitous fall in stock market values marked the end οf the uneven prosperity οf the twenties, and the early 1940s, when global war initiated the long boom, no torrent οf Marxist analyses rushed toward an understanding οf the causes οf capitalist crises in general, or the character οf the Great Depression in particular. In the opening years οf the thirties, the most notable left-wing work on the collapse was Tragic America (1932) by the novelist Theodore Dreiser, who enumerated capitalism's faults but offered little explanation for the cause, timing or depth οf the crisis. Americans fluent in Marxist political economy were also virtually absent from The Encyclopaedia οf the Social Sciences (1930-1935). While open to radical perspectives, contributors, and editors, the Encyclopaedia relied exclusively upon European writers for its sections on "Capitalism," "Crises," "Karl Marx," "Socialist Economics," and "Overproduction." The sole American contributor to a category related to crisis theory or Marxist political economy was Wesley Mitchell, who was neither a Marxist nor a radical and whose entry, "Business Cycles," made not the slightest mention οf Marxian crisis theories. Even by the close οf the decade, the body οf American Marxist economic theory was unimpressive. "There exists in English no reasonably comprehensive analytical study οf Marxian political economy," wrote Paul Sweezy at the outset οf his Theory οf Capitalist Development (1942b, vii). Sweezy had spoken to the paradox οf American Marxism in the 1930s. In the midst οf capitalism's apparent ruin, during a period when radical intellectual life was dominated by a Communist Party with a self-professedly Marxist orientation, in a decade when militant union organizing at the point οf production was the left's central purpose, not one radical intellectual in the United States had produced so much as a serious, thorough overview οf Marxian political economy. Not until recovery was underway and the left discombobulated by war did a young scholar, Sweezy, step forward to produce a solid exposition οf Marxist economic theory. The mystery οf the 1930s, thus, is less the economic obsessions alleged in countless narratives than the paradox that a stunted, inadequate Marxist crisis theory was all that issued from such a moment. The Conservatism οf Economics Why was there so little Marxist crisis theory in the United States during the 1930s? Why was that which did exist so poor in quality? If our expectations are betrayed, it is because ideas do not arise neatly in response to events. The capacity οf theories to emerge and take shape is determined not just by their appropriateness or validity, though merit is a crucial factor, but by the strength and character οf agents which might facilitate their maturation. Complex ideas, that is, require lengthy periods οf development, cultivation, and preservation through cultural and social, which is to say material, institutions. This is particularly the case with economic theory. To attain sophistication, economic thought requires the rigor and technique that only years οf education and training supply. The weakness οf Marxist economic theory in the United States during the 1930s is explained in the first instance by the impediments to it within the two social groupings which might otherwise have generated the intellectual interest, sustained the motivation, and provided the support necessary to its development: the community οf scholars and the radical movement, which in that moment meant the discipline οf economics and the Communist Party. In 1929, when the great crisis struck, there was not a single Marxist teaching economics in a U. S. university. Economics more than any other academic discipline had been purged οf radical voices by administrators and faculty acting under pressure from regional businessmen, conservative alumni, and governing boards. Even H. L. Mencken, who professed to "shrink from Socialists as I shrink from Methodists," pointed with disdain to the orthodox economic consensus οf the twenties as the hired chorus οf a trustee class "with its legs in the stock market and its eyes on the established order." Boards οf trustees, Mencken alleged, kept their tightest grip on political economy since that discipline, "so to speak, hits the employers οf the professors where they live" (1958,150-51,153). For all its bluntness, Mencken's account accurately described the academy οf his day. The measure οf professional autonomy secured by economists in the formative years οf their profession involved a restricted scope οf dissent, outside οf which lay socialism and the cause οf labour. Each οf the four professors who drew national attention as a test case οf academic freedom when his job was threatened between 1880 and 1900--Henry Caner Adams (Cornell), Richard T. Ely (Wisconsin), Edward W. Bernis (University οf Chicago) and E. A. Ross (Stanford)--was an economist whose political activity or advocacy οf social reform landed him in hot water with regents, moneyed alumni, or administrators. This, too, was the case in 1915 when Scott Nearing, an outspoken socialist, was dismissed from the University οf Pennsylvania in one οf the most important transgressions οf academic freedom οf the early twentieth century. The cumulative lesson οf these cases was that economists should avoid controversial ideas and politics. In most cases, the admonition was unnecessary. The elite nature οf higher education and the genteel culture οf scholars in the first decades οf the century insulated them from working-class radicalism. But the memory οf sacrificial predecessors discouraged any undue experimentation, and the concentration οf victims in the economics profession left little room for misinterpretation. That legacy, combined with the ferocious antiradicalism οf the First World War and the Red Scare, sealed the timid fate οf the American economic profession for the 1920s. "If there is a single professor in the United States who teaches political economy and admits himself a Socialist," wrote Upton Sinclair in his blistering appraisal οf university life, The Goose-Step, "that professor is a needle which I have been unable to find in our academic hay-stack." When a discussion club at the University οf Minnesota approached a professor and asked him to speak on Karl Marx, the professor smiled and told the students he wished to remain at the university (Sinclair 1923, 436, 211). Conventional economic doctrines also discouraged the emergence οf Marxism as a credible theoretical perspective in the United States. From the end οf the world war until the 1929 crisis, two major tendencies οf thought wrestled for control οf the discipline: neoclassicism and institutionalism. Neoclassicism--or orthodoxy or marginalism, as it was variously known--was older and stronger, having supplanted classical political economy as the dominant professional paradigm between 1890 and 1910. Its practitioners discarded the labour theory οf value posited by their classical forebears, holding value to be determined by marginal utility, a doctrine that historian Dorothy Ross describes as "an abstraction from and reification οf the liberal capitalist world on the positivist model οf science" (1991,177). In the 1920s, neoclassicists celebrated laissez-faire, fancied the boom permanent, and endorsed Say's Law, the notion that economic activity tends toward a prosperous equilibrium regulated by the interaction οf supply and demand (Stoneman 1979). Opposition to neoclassicism in the United States came primarily from institutionalism, more a range οf thought than a definite school. Institutionalists fancied themselves the heirs οf Thorstein Veblen, the incorrigible iconoclast who virtually alone among major economists οf his generation held fast to dissent despite the repression οf the 1890s. Veblen developed a uniquely anthropological economic method which, in contrast to the static, mechanistic mode οf classical political economy, borrowed biological metaphors to describe economic activity as "evolutionary" or "genetic" and underscored the importance οf institutions--"group habits οf thought," such as private property or competition--in economic development. By the 1920s, institutionalism was less a coherent continuation οf Veblen's project than a hodge-podge οf scholarly endeavours: psychological criticism οf hedonistic assumptions about human motivation; sociological, historical, and anthropological investigations into economic behaviour; descriptions οf business cycles; statistical compilations on industries and phenomena. These projects were linked mainly insofar as they rejected the mechanical assumptions and models οf neoclassical political economy. This looseness permitted widely different approaches to develop in joint cause, and, in that respect, it may have had the effect οf inhibiting the development οf Marxist theory. In Europe, Marxism was the most respected challenge to classical and neoclassical models, but in the United States institutionalism offered a many-sided alternative. Yet institutionalists tended to magnify Veblen's positivist features and to dull his radical insistence that industrial potential was continually frustrated by the waste, incompetence, and senselessness that prevail in class society. Veblen himself was cool to his would-be descendants, and few οf them embraced his call for technical soviets after the Russian Revolution. Parts οf institutionalism were, nonetheless, in harmony with Marxism. Both recognized the emergence οf monopolies in defiance οf classical assumptions about price and competition, rejected laissez-faire as an economic palliative, and emphasized historical and evolutionary transformation. Institutionalism thus did not preclude Marxism, though it may have gratified impulses that might otherwise have led to Marxist conclusions. A final factor in the resistance to Marxist ideas among economists was the profession's general disregard for theory, as manifested in the shift during this period from "political economy" to "economics." Narrow mathematical and statistical modes οf inquiry, which carried theoretical assumptions but eschewed theory as such, gained increasing sway among both neoclassicists and institutionalists, fostering a professional culture resistant to explicitly interpretive perspectives such as Marxism. Although both institutionalism and neoclassicism were at a loss to explain the catastrophe, The American Economic Review did not publish a single Marxist article in the 1930s. In a roundtable discussion on "The Business Depression οf 1930" at the 1931 meeting οf the American Economic Association (A. E. A.), none οf the seven panelists mentioned Marx's name, let alone gave consideration to the possibility that Marxist theory had been confirmed. Only in 1938, as the "second slump" made the depression appear immovable, did an A. E. A. conference panel take up the question οf Marxian economics. Even then, not one οf the four speakers and critics was himself a Marxist. "As an economic theorist," said John Ise οf the University οf Kansas in a comment typical οf the glib tone οf most οf the conversation, "Marx seems generally faulty, or entirely wrong, or occasionally right for the wrong reason" (Ise and Spengler 1938, 17). The Conservatism οf the Communist Party The legacies οf political repression and conceptual conservatism within the economic profession, while significant, do not alone explain the thin results οf Marxian economic theory in the 1930s. The bitter academic witch hunts and conservative-liberal consensus οf the Cold War, for example, did not prevent radicals from gaining a toehold in economics in the 1960s and 1970s. While at the end οf the 1950s, the only Marxist economist remaining at a major university was Paul Baran at Stanford, student radicalism and social upheavals led within roughly a dozen years to the formation οf the Union for Radical Political Economics and The Review οf Radical Political Economics. Why didn't left-wing organizing and upsurge win Marxist economists a similar, grudging acceptance in the university οf the 1930s? Evident dissimilarities provide partial explanation: the comparatively elite status οf universities in the thirties made them less susceptible to challenge than sprawling postwar multiversities; the student movement οf the thirties was peripheral to a larger left devoted to the world beyond the campus, especially to antifascist, African-American, unemployed, and working-class organizing; and few student radicals in the thirties sought to transform campus structures and challenge educational norms as the New Left did. Yet it is also οf critical importance that no single party or organization in the sixties held sway in a manner comparable to the Communist Party οf the thirties. The misfire οf Marxist economic theory in the 1930s cannot wholly be understood apart from the culture and structure οf the American Communist Party. At the beginning οf the Great Depression, the Communist Party was small, but it had the great strategic advantage οf calling the crisis a crisis. Herbert Hoover, by contrast, was convinced that the depression was more psychological than economic and kept predicting a turnaround. "The depression is over," he announced in June 1930. Hoover's blind boosterism was the norm for businessmen and economists bewildered by the disintegration οf the New Era οf the 1920s, which was supposed to have transcended labour strife and the business cycle. "To describe this situation is rather beyond my capacity," sighed one Montgomery Ward executive. "I am unfortunate in having no friends that seem to be able to explain it clearly to me." Not only did the Communist Party face the reality οf the collapse, it offered, unlike disoriented academic economists, a confident assertion οf its causes. William Z. Foster, the steel union leader who rose to lead the Party in the 1920s, had no doubt about the nature οf the depression, which he took as confirmation οf Marx's theory that capitalism consistently drove toward overproduction. "Millions οf workers must go hungry because there is no wheat," Foster testified before a House committee in 1930. "Millions οf workers must go without clothes because the warehouses are full to overflowing with every thing that is needed. Millions οf workers must freeze because there is too much coal. This is the logic οf the capitalist system" (quoted in Cowley 1981, 25, 98, 32-33). Conclusion In closing, the Marxist theory, the cause οf crime is capitalism. The law and criminal justice system are used to protect the interests οf the capitalist elite. In a capitalist system, the means οf production are owned by a small elite (bourgeoisie) and are used to control the working-class labourers (proletariat). Crimes committed by the bourgeoisie are crimes οf domination and repression, and are designed to keep the proletariat in place. Crimes committed by the proletariat are crimes οf accommodation or resistance to the bourgeoisie. Critical criminology also believes that crime is caused by a power struggle in society. Various forms οf this perspective suggest we re-examine the scientific method, rediscover the amount οf pain and suffering in our society, and undertake a quest to discover more peaceful, and possibly religious-or humanistic-based reforms. Works Cited Adamic, Louis. 1938. My America, 1928-1938. New York: Harper. Adams, Arthur B. et al. 1931. "The Business Depression οf 1930: Discussion," American Economic Review 21 (Suppl.): 182-201. Cowley, Malcolm. 1981. The Dream οf the Golden Mountains: Remembering the 1930s. New York: Penguin. Dreiser, Theodore. 1932. Tragic America. New York: Liveright. Foster, John Bellamy, and Henryk Szlajfer. 1984. Introduction. The Faltering Economy. New York: Monthly Review. Mitchell, Wesley. 1970. Business Cycles. New York: Ben Franklin. Ross, Dorothy. 1991. The Origins οf American Social Science. New York: Cambridge. Sinclair, Upton. 1923. The Goose-Step: A Study οf American Education. Pasadena: Upton Sinclair. Stoneman, William A. 1979. A History οf the Economic Analysis οf the Great Depression in America. New York: Garland. Stoneman, William E. 1979. A History οf the Economic Analysis οf the Great Depression in America. New York: Garland. Sweezy, Paul. 1935. "Economics and the Crisis οf Capitalism," Economic Forum 3 (Spring): 71-80. Sweezy, Paul. 1938. "Review οf Socialism, by Ludwig von Mises," Science & Society 2: 265-70. Sweezy, Paul. 1942a. "The Illusion οf the 'Managerial Revolution,'" Science or Society 6: 1-23. Sweezy, Paul. 1942b. The Theory οf Capitalist Development. New York: Oxford. Sweezy, Paul. 1946. "John Maynard Keynes," Science & Society 10: 398-405. Sweezy, Paul. 1972. Modern Capitalism. New York: Monthly Review. Veblen, Thorstein. 1909. "The Limitations οf Marginal Utility," Journal οf Political Economy 17: 620-36. Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism f the Communist Party Coursework, n.d.)
Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism f the Communist Party Coursework. Retrieved from https://studentshare.org/macro-microeconomics/1710756-subject-political-science-in-1989-some-observers-claimed-that-marxism-was-obsolete-what-if-any-analytical-insights-can-marxist-political-economy-still-provi
(Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism F the Communist Party Coursework)
Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism F the Communist Party Coursework. https://studentshare.org/macro-microeconomics/1710756-subject-political-science-in-1989-some-observers-claimed-that-marxism-was-obsolete-what-if-any-analytical-insights-can-marxist-political-economy-still-provi.
“Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism F the Communist Party Coursework”. https://studentshare.org/macro-microeconomics/1710756-subject-political-science-in-1989-some-observers-claimed-that-marxism-was-obsolete-what-if-any-analytical-insights-can-marxist-political-economy-still-provi.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF Marxist Political Economy, the Conservatism f the Communist Party

Organization of Factors of Production

Land, labor, and capital are exploited for the production of goods and services in the economy to constitute the national income.... These factors of production are scattered within the economy and thus the need for organization of these factors of production.... Normally, countries seek to redesign their social, political and legal institutions to alter their impact for the improvement of the economy.... Social, political, economic and legal institutions in a country affect the economic growth both positively and negatively....
7 Pages (1750 words) Assignment

Zedong and Xiaoping Different Ideology and One Same Goal

Along with Zhou Enlai, Zhu De and Lin Biao, Mao Zedong was a founder-member of Chinese communist party (CPP) when it was established in 1921 (bbc.... Mao's ushering into Marxism could be attributed to his devoted reading of Marx's “the communist Manifesto” while he worked in the University Library (bbc.... Consequently, Mao led his followers and the communist Red Army in the legendary 6,000 mile retreat “Long March” to Northwest China “to establish a new base” (“Mao Zedong”)....
3 Pages (750 words) Essay

What are the likely implications of further growth in economic inequalities within countries

А comparatively moderate hypothesis argues that economic inequality would alter as financial growth amends or more specifically; economic inequality would increase initially and then decrease with financial growth.... hellip; What are the likely implications of further growth in economic inequalities within countries?...
9 Pages (2250 words) Essay

What were the idealistic qualities of communism

As a youth leader he had taken part in violent attacks and strikes and he continued with the same working style on getting the supreme position of power in the communist hierarchy in Russia.... The principle enunciated by Marx was followed by Russian communist leadership, "from each according to his ability, to each according to his needs”.... communist ideology did not thrive under Stalin and people suffered much.... He initiated the five year plans for development of Russian economy, introduced collective farming, and took away land from the rich farmers to created state-owned farms....
7 Pages (1750 words) Research Paper

The Future of Radical Politics by Gidden

Giddens claims that although modernity has made its sure headway, the imperative significance of traditionalism and conservatism could never be negated or refuted at any cost.... Therefore, power appears to be shifting from modernity to radicalism-conservatism in various parts of the globe, and the developed nations have to make strong decisions in order to combat with the opposition from radicals.... One of the primary reasons behind exploring the work under review includes the writer's profound elaboration of political thoughtfulness on the global issues that have been in vogue in the modern times for the last few decades on the one side, and the setbacks and challenges that the age-old notions refer to international relations and political experience at the hands of the rival groups and communities on the other side....
6 Pages (1500 words) Essay

The Discovery Of Society by Randall Collins and Michael Makowsky

The researcher also presents an analysis of the communist Manifesto and states that without Lenin, Stalin and Mao, the history of 20th century would have been very different, although almost certainly barely less disordered or bloody.... The triumph of free-market economic theories all through the world and the fall down of the communist states of the Soviet Union and Eastern Europe....
10 Pages (2500 words) Essay

How did the relationship between individual and state change over the course of the twentieth century

The Soviet Union communism was based on Marxism–Leninism ideology which held that the policies of understanding social life were the prevalent truths since the party was enlightened.... In the 19th century, most nations across Europe, North America and Spanish America adopted liberalism which opposed traditional conservatism and promoted representative democracy and the rule of law in government.... Fascism was an economic system in the 1920s and 1930s that was capitalist in which the state dictated all aspects of the economy....
2 Pages (500 words) Essay

A Critical Analysis of Ideology In America by Christopher Ellis and James Stimson

conservatism is an aristocratic ideology given the many similarities between them.... conservatism advocates for the preservation of the best in society with an opposing view on the effecting of radical changes.... conservatism has nine schools of thought under it.... They are liberal conservatism, conservative liberalism, libertarian conservatism, fiscal conservatism, green conservatism, national and traditional conservatism, cultural and social conservatism, religious conservatism, and progressive conservatism....
6 Pages (1500 words) Book Report/Review
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us