StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

Kantian Ethics: A Comparative Analysis of Kant's Moral Theory - Book Report/Review Example

Cite this document
Summary
This book review "Kantian Ethics: A Comparative Analysis of Kant's Moral Theory" focuses on the strategies used for justifying moral theories, as this is generally where the theorists go their separate ways in constructing the supreme principle of morality…
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER96.8% of users find it useful
Kantian Ethics: A Comparative Analysis of Kants Moral Theory
Read Text Preview

Extract of sample "Kantian Ethics: A Comparative Analysis of Kant's Moral Theory"

Running Head: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS OF KANT'S MORAL THEORY Kantian Ethics: A Comparative Analysis of Kant's Moral Theory (Institution's Name) Kantian Ethics: A Comparative Analysis of Kant's Moral Theory Introduction This essay deals with the identification of any possible element of Kant's work in moral philosophy which can be used as a substantial theoretical source for the support of other theories of justification. Thus, it is necessary to compare Kant's views about moral judgements with each of the theorists discussed below, and identify the similarities and differences each theory have in light of Kant's. This paper will focus on the strategies used for justifying moral theories, as this is generally where the theorists go their separate ways in constructing the supreme principle of morality. As such each theory may yield different answers to the three questions raised under morality: 1) Authoritative question: Why ought I be moral 2) Substantive question: Which interest ought I to take favourable account of 3) Distributive question: Whose interest ought I to take favourable account of In order to achieve the above task the paper has been divided in four parts. Firstly it is important to identify the methods of justification used by Kant in Groundwork of Metaphysics of Moral. A general overview is also made regarding the value of Kant's work for the researchers in the area of moral philosophy. From that the second part of this essay refers to the theories of justification used by other philosophers, namely Rawls and Hare. This essay would argue that although many of Kant's concepts are used, the extent to which they served as models of theory justification is rather some degree of. The idea of (preference) utilitarianism is also presented in this part in order to explain the stages of development of moral theory in the history. Part Three evaluates the possible relation between the methods of justification used by Kant and those applied by D. Gauthier and A. Gewirth. It is submitted that both share some similarities with Kant's view that all rational being must reason morally, but differ in their ways of justifying such claim, and ultimately yield a different conclusion as to Kant's. (i.e. a different supreme principle of morality) Finally, it is critical to summarise the views presented in the above two parts in an effort to identify the possible relation between Kant's moral theory and those by other theorists in the area of moral philosophy. As this paper deals with the Kantian Moral Theory, it is very important to have a clear idea of the 'Moral Theory'. Firstly, morality concerns conduct. It is about what a person ought to do, and how one's actions reflect morality. Nevertheless, this does not distinguish morality from other types of knowledge, for mathematics and law also concern with our conduct. Secondly, moral problems are normative, i.e. they relates to a typical standard or rules by affirming how things should or ought to be and how to value them. This is in sharp contrast with descriptive theory, which pertains to describing reality. Thirdly, even normative problems concern what ought to be done, not all normative problems can be described as normal. As a result, the task is to make a distinction moral problems from non-moral normative problems. With this foundational idea of morality in mind, we can now give a definition of morality in order to evaluate how 'moral' the theories to be discussed are. Something is 'morally ought to be' if and only if the 'ought to be' is propounded as 1. Action-guiding - X intends this to guide action. 2. Other-addressing - addresses to somebody other than the one saying it (X). 3. Other-regarding - this is the reason why it is ought to be because some outer element is involved to others than X. 4. Co natively independent - independent of desire, i.e. one has to do it whether he wants to or not. 5. Categorically binding - overrides all prescription that is not within one. to 4., i.e. moral ought to's override other kinds of ought to's. The two focus elements of this paper in analysing each moral theory shall pertain to the following three questions; 1. Authoritative Question: 'Why ought I to be moral' In other words, why my actions ought to be guided by moral principles, or accept the five conditions of morality 2. Substantive Question: 'Which interest ought I to take favourable account of' 3. Distributive Question: 'Whose interest ought I to take favourable account of' This paper is a discussion of meta-ethical theories (as opposed to normative moral theories), where each theory may differ depending on how they define morality; analyse key moral concepts, e.g. 'good', 'bad', 'rights', 'duties', 'right', 'wrong', and more importantly, how they answer the authoritative question. Hence, this paper shall discuss only the first question, as this paper focuses on the question of whether rational agents must reason morally, by looking at Kant's Groundwork and comparing his theory with others to find out. Kant was born on April 22, 1724, in the Prussian city of KSnigsberg (today Kaliningrad, Russia), the fourth of six children.( Borowski, 1969) After attending the Collegium Fridericianum from 1732 to 1740, he enrolled at the University of KSnigsberg in the faculty of philosophy. Kant, in his Groundwork, has employed two justificatory methods with the 'sole aim' of to 'seek out and establish the supreme principle of morality' (or indeed, of practical reasoning). But before moving on to these two entirely different methods, it should be noted that Kant repeatedly insists that the premise must remain a priori, that is, any knowledge gained must be without appealing to any experience. Courage or justice are always shaping and inspiring actions a person choose to do because they are just or courageous, but they are there imperfectly, as images or imitations. If a person seek to do what someone be aware of to be right, someone seek something whose presence and power cannot be fully active in ordinary things, in a battle or a code of laws, say, but only for thought. This paper shall discuss the Kantian Moral Theory in the light of the various other similar theories presented by other philosophers during and after Kant's time. Discussion Part One - Kant's Moral Theory Kant begins the substantive discussion of morality in his most widely read practical work, the Groundwork, by claiming that our common view is that only a good will could be considered good without limitation.( Mary, 1996) All other goods, even virtues, can be misused; even complete satisfaction can produce arrogance. This means that the good will and nothing else must be the heart of moral duty, because our everyday view is that moral duty is obligatory, and allows no exceptions. Is it not true, however, that we often say commonsensical that a good will without talent or equipment is feckless, that uninformed good will can be uselessly meddlesome, that good will together with poor judgment is harmful, and that the road to hell is paved with good intentions If the standard for judging what is good is the result, that is to say, or if the standard is our usual unanalyzed conglomeration of intention and result, the good will is not altogether good. We can put this problem in another way by saying that the goodness of a good will is not commonsensical separable from its object, from what it wills or intends. (Regis) Can the will or intention to be moderate in pursuing pleasure, for example, be divorced from understanding and experiencing what the attraction of pleasure or appropriate pleasure is At the least, some grasp of an abstract sense or content of good is needed to make the "good" that the good will is willing intelligible: ordinarily, the goodness of the good will apart from its objects cannot in fact be described meaningfully without implicitly accepting some notion of the goodness of its object. (Beyleveld) As Kant develops his argument beyond this first commonsensical beginning, he attempts to make truly moral commands as self-enclosed as possible, in the sense that the propriety of the command loses any reference to something outside the command itself. The mere universal form of the maxim that recommends an action, he argues, is what guarantees that following it is moral, apart from the end or goals that the maxim originally was intended to reach or bring about.( Mary, 1996) In this sense, the starting point of his argument--that only a good will is altogether good--remains fundamental and is even radicalized. Ultimately, Kant attempts to grasp the goodness of the good will, its morality, in terms built up solely from the free, universalizable incentive of will itself. This, however, leaves a serious question whether the understanding on which Kant settles about what is choice worthy or good is not too narrow or, finally, unintelligible, or, at the least, whether he implicitly has in mind some notion of goodness that in fact is not meaningful apart from the objects they will chooses or intends, just as we commonsensical cannot in fact say what we mean by a good intention without at some point having in mind a view of the goodness of what we are trying to bring about, so, too, would Kant's radical defence of the goodness of free will seem to be similarly dependent. It is not clear, in other words, that Kant's view of moral intention correctly grasps the common framework of goodness and choice worthiness that it explicates. (Borowski, 1969) The heart of Kant's actual understanding of morality revolves around several thoughts and concepts that he often fails to describe at any length: form, end, causality, freedom, and universality. Kant's view is that a moral action must be chosen for a moral reason. A moral reason is one in which the maxim recommending the action is completely universalizable. If it is completely universalizable, it is purely formal and reasonable, and could--or, indeed, must--be selected by any simply reasonable being, such as God. No material end, on the other hand, can be certainly desirable. (Korsgaard, Ch 1-4) To determine or cause oneself by a universalized maxim, moreover, is to determine one freely. More precisely, it is not to be determined by what is outside oneself, by natural causes or laws of motion. It is to determine one's own actions, to push oneself along as one's own efficient cause. ( Borowski, 1969; Evdokimov, 1986) The scholarly controversy concerns whether by free action Kant means only moral action, action in accord with a successfully universalized maxim, or whether he believes there is a "free choice" (Wilbur) that precedes moral choice and is governed either by moral choice or by maxims rooted in calculation determined by our attraction to what might satisfy our desires.(Paul, 1998) One reason this question is hard to decide is because Kant says little about freedom generally, and what he does say is mostly in the context of describing moral choice. Freedom is negative if we are not determined by desires, and positive if we are self-determined morally. Negative freedom is not different from positive freedom, but only how positive freedom looks in terms of desires that do not determine it. Clearly, Kant does not intend freedom to mean arbitrariness because it is legislating the moral law for oneself, that is, allowing it to determine one's choice or making it the law for oneself by successfully universalizing the maxim that commands one's action. (Bernard) Freedom is not creating the law or acting lawlessly. However, the exact status of self-determination or self-control in general is unclear: if it means nothing other than moral determination, then we are indeed free only when we are moral and there is, strictly, no other freedom. If self-determination is a wider concept, however, Kant has said nothing about what it might be or mean in "free choice," what the possibilities are that need to be considered, and so on. Positively, that is to say, Kant has not differentiated it from arbitrariness or, indeed, given it any intelligible status at all. This issue also faces us if we look at freedom not as self-determination but simply as being undetermined or unchained, that is, if we do not look from the standpoint of control or initiating movement but see freedom as being unbound or unhindered. (Mary, 1991) For Kant gives no substantive description of this state or situation such that we could understand how, qua free choice, it stands undetermined (between morality and immorality, say, or simply standing) nor, therefore, how it could control or direct itself or be controlled or directed. Here too Kant does not discuss the range of possibilities, nor does he clarify if this language of freedom as not being hindered or controlled, not being held back or pushed forward, as it were, is the full way to grasp freedom. In his long discussion of evil in Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, the one thing Kant never makes precisely dear is how the free choice of evil is possible in terms of freedom (or how it is determined by freedom), only that it happens. These issues are important to Kant's moral thought because if freedom is present outside moral choice, a central ground for Kant's arguing that his view alone captures morality because it alone captures the freedom that moral action must have would be untrue, or, at least, insufficiently demonstrated. Some of Kant's power would be dissipated. (Paton) Beyond this, of course, the possibility of moral choice would need to be explicated or grasped in terms of the other broader areas that make freedom more generally intelligible. If free choice is arbitrary, and morality can (or cannot) be freely chosen, morality may at root be arbitrary. If morality rests on other grounds of freedom, of not being controlled or hindered, and is not arbitrary, moral reason would nonetheless incompletely determine our freedom; moral choice would not be the only self-determination. (Vallentyne) If morality can retain its universal obligatory character within free choice which is a process or act that in some way is neither arbitrary nor moral by being, or being grounded in, another set of reasons, this too needs explicating. If, however, Kant in fact means that freedom strictly is moral choice and nothing else, that the appearance of free choice simply is just that, an appearance rooted in moral purity, then questions about our responsibility for choosing immorally remain difficult. How can we freely will evil if the only true freedom is moral choice( Kant, 1998) Related issues cloud Kant's analysis of the reason, formality and causality involved in morality. These issues are pertinent to the freedom of moral choice itself, whatever our questions about freedom in Kant more broadly. Kant argues that the self-determination of moral freedom is self-causality. Causality is efficient causality operating according to universal laws. However, is this alone what causality is Traditionally, one speaks of formal, final, and material, as well as of efficient causality. Might moral causality be of another kind, or also of another kind One might reply that we are ignoring here Kant's critique of pure reason. Obviously, we are far from fully exploring each element of Kant's thought. Our point is simply that he does not himself explore alternate ways to consider form, reason, freedom, ends, and their connection, and that important alternatives exist. Part Two - Hare and Rawls Like Kant, Hare and Rawls both support rational non-cognistivism. However, unlike Kant, both are weak rationalists, i.e. the authoritative question is not being answered by either Hare or Rawls, while Kant did so in Chapter III. Hare shows similarities by using the conceptual analysis of morality as Kant did in Chapter I and II (criteria of rationality - pure logic). However, this is not enough for him to be claimed as a Kantian. His theory is teleological, while Kant's is Deontological. Moral 'ought' will be explained here, particularly its universailability, prescriptively and overridingness. The third element, which distinguishes morality, does not any play part in Hare's justification while Kant did so by saying it is categorically binding. In addition, the logical principle of universalizability will be introduced. It is concluded that Hare's theory is what Kant tends to utilise in Chapter I and II, but with Hare having a different strategy, which leads to a different conclusion and a different set of principles. (Although both have the issue of impartiality, which will be discussed in Part three.) Hare is best described as a preference utilitarian and this is where utilitarianism will be compared with Kant. (Daniels) This part will also examine the question of whether Kant could have been a utilitarian. Hare contended that although Kant is not a utilitarian ultimately, he could have become one. If this is so, then Hare and Kant may not have differed much after all. Rawls is one of the most characteristic cases of Kant's influence which accepts the issue of 'morality' as expressed by Kant supporting particularly the value of 'individual morality' which interacts continuously with the social justice. More specifically in accordance with Rawls 'a society united on a reasonable form of utilitarianism, or on the reasonable liberalisms of Kant, would likewise require the sanctions of state power to remain so' (Rawls, 1996, 38). Rawls's theory contains an impartial viewpoint, requiring agents to consider the interests of others. These moral constraints are imposed on agents because of the original position we have to put ourselves in. However, he does not provide a reason for adopting his moral viewpoint. This makes him a weak rationalist by ignoring the authoritative question, which Kant justifies in Chapter 3. It is argued that the use of an entirely and deliberately artificial device means he did not justify his principles by conceptual analysis of the moral viewpoint (as Kant did in Chapter 1 and two), but moral contractarianism. A number of Rawls's religious critics have taken him to task for his idea of public reason, arguing either that it "excludes the religious by drawing the boundaries of public reason so that comprehensive religious doctrines fall outside them for the most part" or that the bifurcation of public and private reason marginalizes those "for whom it is a matter of religions conviction that they ought to strive for a religiously integrated existence."(Philip, Weithman, ed., and Nicholas) In his later essay, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," Rawls moves toward an accommodation of these critics, conceding that "reasonable comprehensive doctrines, religious or nonreligious, may be introduced in public political discussion at any time, provided that in due course proper political reasons--and not reasons given solely by comprehensive doctrines--are presented that are sufficient to support whatever the comprehensive doctrines introduced are said to support."( Rawls) However, the ultimate recourse to public reason remains a moral duty, not simply a matter of prudential political strategy. Those moved primarily by religious reasons must still be prepared to express themselves in terms of public reason. (Beyleveld, Ch. 5) Through his emphasis on those in formal positions of political authority, Rawls also, to some degree, excuses citizens from the requirement that their personal political deliberations be conducted in terms of public reason as well.( Rawls, 133-136) There remain problems, even with Rawls's modified and more accommodating conception of public reason. Whether part of Rawls's intention or not, the strictures of the public arena--the implicit or explicit claim that it is backward or impermissible or in bad taste to advance religious claims or arguments in public(Rorty, 1999)--run the risk of undermining the vitality and profundity of religious discourse.( Wolterstorff, 178, 179) What is authoritative in the public arena may well become authoritative in many or most aspects of our lives. In addition, if what is authoritative is as thin as Rawls's political conception, we run the risk of greatly impoverishing our intellectual and moral lives as individuals, members of associations, and citizens. Part Three - Gauthier and Gewirth Gauthier (as well as Locke, Kant, and Nozick) offers only a partial justification of private ownership. Not only does Gauthier never consider the possibility that other forms of ownership might have the same results as private ownership but, indeed, there are other forms of ownership, which do have the same result. That Gauthier must ground private ownership upon a state-of-nature original appropriation is integral to his method as he sees it. Gauthier considers morality to be the product of agreement for cooperative interaction which is required to remedy the (essential) imperfections of the free market.( David, p. 84, 1986) Both the free market, as a morally free zone, and cooperative agreements to internalize external costs presuppose an impartial (but not equal) initial bargaining position of factor endowments.( David, p. 86 & p.130, 1986) This is to say that markets presuppose people own something to exchange in the market and that bargaining presupposes that people start at some position of strength or weakness from which they may assess the value of various possible agreements. Gauthier argues that in order for the outputs from the free market and from agreements to be "moralized," the inputs--i.e., the initial position--must be proven impartial. Gauthier rejects an equal initial position, such as John Rawls's, because it permits free riders.( David, p. 151 and p. 201, 1986) Original, impartial private appropriation is the necessary moral foundation, which Gauthier believes he needs in order to "moralize" the outputs of the free market and of cooperative agreements. (Rawls) Gewirth holds that human action is both voluntary and purposive. In respect of its purposiveness, the agent sees the goal of the action as some good and this good as ultimately justifying the action. Therefore, Gewirth's first claim is that from the agent's point of view his purpose justifies his action. His second claim is that, ipso facto, the agent implicitly claims that, at least-prima facie, he has a right to do the action. Besides the reasons integral to Gauthier's theory, it must be noticed that (in general) gift, bequest, and exchange are incomplete as criteria of title. Each presupposes some additional criterion of title, which would originally distribute legitimate title over things so that individuals could then transfer title by gift, bequest, or exchange. Social contract theorists have solved the problem of original distribution in two different ways. Some have made the distribution prior to the contract, while others have made the distribution part of the contract. Rawls and Hobbes make the distribution a result of the social contract. (Smart and Williams) In the Leviathan, Hobbes's contract empowers the sovereign to make original distribution as well as to make the rules governing subsequent transfers.( Thomas, 1950) Rawls makes the communal ownership of talents and abilities part of the contract. By contrast, Hume and Locke locate the original distribution in what exist prior to the convention or contract. For Hume, "present possession" at the time of the convention is "the natural expedient" for making the original distribution.( David, 1964) Locke, as is well known, employs labour on what is unwonted as the criterion for his initial distribution. Gauthier, like Hume and Locke, adopts the precontract rather than the contract-dependent methodology. Gauthier's justification of private ownership rests upon the following illustration. Imagine that several persons inhabit an island where the land and resources, in effect, constitute a commons available to all. Use is in dividable, each family provides primarily for its own needs, and interaction is non-cooperative. Suppose that Eve, the head of one of the families, is aware that planned, intensive cultivation would make the land more productive, so that she proposes to take a certain area of the island for her exclusive use in order that her family may benefit by maximizing its productivity. She seeks, therefore, an exclusive right to a certain portion of the island. Eve seeks the security of tenure which market compensation, rather than full compensation, confers. (Gauthier) Full compensation, according to Gauthier, is compensation, which leaves a person without any net loss in utility. Market compensation would be compensation at the market price she might realize through exchange. Eve seeks the more comprehensive protection which a right in the product of her labour would realize.(Gauthier, pp. 63-65, 1974) Eve intends to better her family's situation through a system of rights that determine her endowment for prospective market and cooperative interaction. Gauthier argues that Eve's appropriation need not be brought about by worsening the situation of the other islanders. (Guyer, Ch.6) While Eve might seek to appropriate a too-large portion of the island, which would violate the Locke and proviso against worsening the situation of others, there might be sufficiently abundant land such that she need not worsen the situation of others. (Gewirth) Eve's appropriation might be small enough and her increased productivity might be sufficiently large so that her fellow islanders might be better off through exchanges with her than they were before she privately appropriated her plot of land. Gauthier concludes his derivation by showing that if Eve gives up her rights to the remaining commons and if Eve's increased, productivity would be beneficial to her as well as to others, then her exclusive rights of possession are justified: others may benefit themselves, and Eve is, in Gauthier's words, "the great benefactress of human kind."( Gauthier, pp. 214-17, 1989) That Karl, Rosa, and Friedrich agree to cooperate does not violate Gauthier's assumptions about human motivation. Gauthier defends a subjective theory of value. A person's considered preferences determine her reasons for choice and action. Even though Gauthier's basic motivational assumption is the subjective theory of value, he sometimes describes his assumptions about the rationality of choices as "self-interested" or "nontuistic." Several commentators have noted that Gauthier's descriptions are not equivalent.( Baler, pp. 35-44; 1988 and Laurence, pp. 160-70) A subjective theory of value does not logically limit a person's motivation only to choices that are self-interested or non-touristic. Someone may prefer to advance the interests of others--e.g., the interests of friends and loved-ones. Self-interest and non-truism, of course, limit the content of preferences. Gauthier has recently said that his self-interest assumption is to prevent "double-counting" in utility calculations; such a practice would count some preferences twice and thus upset Pareto optimality.( Gauthier, p. 214.) Gauthier's reply does not explain why the decision by Karl, Rosa, and Friedrich to cooperate need violate his assumption, whether it is described as the subjective theory of value or as self-interested. (Hare) If Karl, Rosa, and Friedrich prefer to cooperate, then there is no incompatibility with a subjective theory of value. Karl's, Rosa's, and Friedrich's choice to cooperate also need not violate either the assumption of self-interest or of non-truism. Cooperation can be beneficial. Rational, self-interested people can individually benefit from cooperation. Gauthier's argument in Morals by Agreement depends upon this. Gauthier's decision to base the initial position upon a private appropriation is therefore one plausible choice, but it is not the only logical or best one. Private ownership and exchange is one way individuals may benefit, but it is not the only way. Working together and sharing the increased productivity is another. Cooperation is not incompatible with assumptions about self-interest or non-truism. Any moral justification of a form of ownership grounded upon an original act of appropriation in a state of nature must show not only that the particular form is thus grounded, but also that no other form can be so grounded. Using private ownership as an example, it is not sufficient to show that private ownership can be grounded on original appropriation in a state of nature; the argument must also show that no other form of ownership, such as communal ownership, can also fulfil the relevant standard of justification. Suppose that a Gauthier or a Locke tries to prove that private ownership based upon original private appropriation produces more utility or benefit to each individual than the state of nature in which land and resources in effect constitute a commons available to all. While this argument may seem to justify private ownership, the argument does not show that only private ownership is morally justified. (Guyer, Ch.10) There may be other forms of ownership, such as cooperative collective ownership or private usufruct, which also produce more utility or benefit than a state of nature in which land and resources are a commons available to all. If the standard of justification is the production of greater benefit or utility for each than the state-of-nature commons, then private ownership, private usufruct, and collective cooperative ownership may be morally justified. The problem is that this state-of-nature justification shows all three to be justified, which means that this state-of-nature argument cannot be used to decide which of the three is morally preferable. A complete justification would have to show that private ownership and only private ownership fulfils the standard of justification. Other forms of ownership must therefore be examined and shown not to fulfil the standards. Arguments which show that private ownership (or any other form) is grounded upon original appropriation, but which fail to show that only private ownership (or some other form) is so grounded, therefore one shall call partial justifications. The result of this amalgamating of efficient, final, and formal cause is that the other elements of causality, (or, if causality seems to us always to mean efficient causality, of living within and for grounds) are not discussed independently. Form as Plato or Hegel means it, for example, does not enter the discussion. Consider, for example, the Platonic argument that "form" is always present in my actions because these are guided by my discourse or opinion, but present imperfectly or incompletely. Someone seek justice, is oriented to it, is formed by it, and freely act on it as a person reasonably but imperfectly grasp it. Form of this sort is not universal as it is in Kant, but it is hardly unintelligible. If freedom means seeing the reason in something and acting for that reason and nothing else, it is unclear why this formality is any less clear than the universal moral shaping that Kant has in mind. Conclusion Therefore, it cannot be concluded that nor can Kant argue that cooperation between Karl, Friedrich, and Rosa is excluded because it would be a contract before the social contract. First, as critics remarked earlier, social contract theorists have dealt with the problem of initial distribution by both pre-contract and contract-dependent methodologies. Nothing in the idea of a social contract necessitates a pre-contract methodology, rather than a contract-dependent one. Second, Gauthier's own method must permit pre-contract agreements and cooperation, both of which are presupposed by the free market which Gauthier believes exists prior to and is the reason for morals by agreement Gauthier's attempt at justifying private ownership from an original appropriation in the state of nature fails to produce a complete justification of private ownership, which shows that private ownership, and only private ownership is morally justifiable. His justification is partial because his arguments fail to exclude other possible forms of ownership. Gauthier is not unique in this respect. Critics know of no major philosopher who has carefully compared the implications of different forms of ownership in state of nature conditions. It is not a sufficient proof to establish merely that private ownership is an improvement upon the state of nature. A complete justification must actually show that no other possible form of ownership can do as well. References Avon, T. Foundation of risk analysis, a knowledge and decision-oriented perspective, Wiley, New York (2003). Benjamin, J.R. and Cornell, A. Probability, statistics, decisions for civil engineers, McGraw-Hill, Inc, New York, USA (1970). Bernard, W Utilitariansim and Beyond Beyleveld, D Dialectical Necessity of Morality Beyleveld, D Human Dignity in Bioethics and Biolaw Ch.5 Borowski LE, Jachmann RB, Wasianski EACh. Immanuel Kant. Sein Leben in Darstellungen von Zeitgenossen. 1912. Italian translation by Pocar E. La vita di Immanuel Kant. Bari: Editori Laterza, 1969. Daniels, N Reading Rawls David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986)., p. 84. David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986)., p. 86 and p. 130. David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986)., p. 151 and p. 201. David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1964), p. 490, and Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1963), p. 195. Evdokimov PP. Immanuel Kant's disease. Klin Med (Mosk) 1986; 64: 148-50. Gauthier, D Morals by Agreement Gauthier, David "Morality, Rational Choice, and Semantic Representation," The New Social Contract, p. 214. Gauthier, p. 211. Gauthier also cites Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), pp. 63-65. Gauthier, pp. 214-17. In his most recent book, The Libertarian Idea (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989), Gewirth, A Reason and Morality Guyer, P. The Cambridge companion to Kant, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge UK (1992). Guyer, Paul Kant on Freedom, Law and Happiness Ch.6 Guyer, Paul The Cambridge Companian to Kant, Ch.10 Hare, RM Moral Thinking Kant, Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, Allan Wood and George di Giovanni, trans, and eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 6:32. Korsgaard, C Creating the Kingdom of Ends, Ch.1-4 Kurt Baler, "Rationality, Value, and Preference," The New Social Contract, ed. Ellen Frankel Paul et al. (Oxford: Basic Blackwell, 1988), pp. 35-44. Laurence Thomas, "Rationality and Affectivity: The Metaphysics of The Moral Self," The New Social Contract, pp. 160-70. Christopher W. Morris, "The Relation Between Self-Interest and Justice in Contractarian Ethics," The New Social Contract, pp. 119-48. Lindley, D.V. Making decisions, Wiley, New York (1985). Mary Gregor, trans., Kant's Metaphysics of Morals (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991) also contain good bibliographies. Mary J. Gregor in Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996). 4:393; 4:437. Paton, H Kant's Groundwork of Metaphysics of Morals Paul Guyer, ed., Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998). Philip L. Quinn, "Political Liberalisms and their Exclusions of the Religious," in Weithman, ed., Religion and Contemporary Liberalism, 148; and Nicholas Wolterstorff, "Why We Should Reject What Liberalism Tells Us about Speaking and Acting in Public for Religious Reasons," in Weithman, 177. Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," 152. Rawls, Cf. "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," 133-136, with the earlier formulation in Political Liberalism, 215. Rawls, J A Theory of Justice Regis Jr Edward, Gewirth's Ethical Rationalism Rorty,Richard; "Religion as a Conversation Stopper," in Rorty, Philosophy and Social Hope (Harmondsworth, England: Penguin, 1999), 168-174. Skorupsle, J. The Cambridge companion to mill, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge UK (1998). Smart JJC and Williams, B Utilitarianism For and Against Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (New York: Everyman Library, 1950), p. 210. Vallentyne, P Contractarianism and Rational Choice Wolterstorff, "Why We Should," in Weithman, 178, 179. Bibliography Alford, C. Fred. 1997. What Evil Means to Us. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Alford, C. Fred. 1997. "The Political Psychology of Evil." Political Psychology 18:1-15. Anscombe, G.E.M. 1981. The Collected Philosophical Papers of G.E.M. Anscombe. Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press. Aristotle. 1953. Ethics: The Nichomachean Ethics. Translated by J. A. K. Thomson. London: Unwin and Allen. Aronson, E., J. Cohen, and P. Nail. 1998. "Self-Affirmation Theory: An Update and Appraisal." In Cognitive Dissonance Theory: Revival with Revisions and Controversies, ed. E. Harmon-Jones and J. S. Mills. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Aronson, E., T. D. Wilson, and R. M. Akert. 1974/1999. Social Psychology. New York: Longman-Addison Wesley. Aronson, Eliot, and J. Mills. 1959. "The Effect of Severity of Initiation on Liking for a Group." Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 59:177-181. Aronson, Eliot. 1968, "Dissonance Theory: Progress and Problems." In Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook, ed. R. P. Abelson et al. Chicago: Rand McNally. Aronson, Eliot. 1969. "The Theory of Cognitive Dissonance: A Current Perspective." In Advances in Experimental Social Psychology. vol. 4, ed. L. Berkowitz. New York: Academic Press. Aronson, Eliot. 1992. "The Return of the Repressed: Dissonance Theory Makes a Comeback." Psychological Inquiry 3:303-311. Aronson, Eliot. 1998. "Dissonance, Hypocrisy, and the Self-Concept." In Cognitive Dissonance Theory: Revival with Revisions and Controversies, ed. E. Harmon-Jones and J.S. Mills. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Baier, Annette. 1994. Moral Prejudice: Essays on Ethics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Bal, Mieke, Jonathan Crewe, and Leo Spitzer, ed. 1999. Acts of Memory: Cultural Recall in the Present. Hanover, N.H.: University Press of New England. Bal, Mieke. 1985. Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative. Translated by Christine von Boheemen. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Bal, Mieke. 1991. On Story-telling: Essays in Narratology. Ed. David Jobling. Sonoma, Calif.: Polebridge Press. Baumeister, R. E 1998. "The Self." In The Handbook of Social Psychology. 4th ed., ed. D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, and G. Lindzey. New York: McGraw-Hill. Bertenthal, B. L., and K. W. Fischer. 1978. "Development of Self-Recognition in the Infant." Developmental Psychology 14:44-50. Bettelheim, B. 1982. Freud and Man's Soul. New York: Knopf. Bickerton, D. 1975. Dynamics of a Creole System. New York: Cambridge University Press. Bickerton, D. 1995. Language and Human Behavior. Seattle: University of Washington Press. Blasi, A. 1980. "Bridging Moral Cognition and Moral Action: A Critical Review of the Literature." Psychological Bulletin 88:1-45. Blasi, A. 1988. "Identity and Development of the Self." In Self, Ego and Identity: Integrative Approaches, ed. D. K. Lapsley and F. C. Power. New York: Springer-Verlaag. Blasi, A. 1993. "The Development of Identity: Some Implications for Moral Functioning." In The Moral Self, ed. G. G. Noam and T. E.Wren. Cambridge: MIT Press. Blasi, A. 1995. "A Moral Understanding and the Moral Personality: The Process of Moral Integration" In Moral Development: An Introduction, ed. W.M. Kurtines and J.L. Gewirtz. Boston: Allyn and Bacon. Brehm, J. W. 1956. "Postdecision Changes in the Desirability of Alternatives." Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 52: 384-389. Brehm, J. W., and A. R. Cohen. 1962. Experiments in Cognitive Dissonance. New York: Wiley. Browning, C. 1992. Ordinary Men: Reserve Order Police Battalion 101 and the Final Solution in Poland. New York: Aaron Asher/HarperCollins. Campbell, Donald. 1990. "Self-Esteem and Clarity of the Self-Concept." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59:941-951. Chomsky, Noam. 1966. Cartesian Linguistics: A Chapter in the History of Rationalist Thought. New York: Harper and Row. Chomsky, Noam. 1968. Language and Mind. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World. Chomsky, Noam. 1988. Language and Problems of Knowledge: The Managua Lectures. Cambridge: MIT Press. Chomsky, Noam. 1986. Knowledge of Language. Its Nature, Origin, and Use. New York: Praeger. Colby, A., and Damon, W. 1992. Some Do Care. New York: Free Press. Colby, A., and Damon, W. 1993. "The Unity of Self and Morality in the Development of Extraordinary Moral Commitment." In The Moral Self, ed. G. G. Noam and T. E. Wren. Cambridge: MIT Press. Cooper, J. 1980. "Reducing Fears and Increasing Assertiveness: The Role of Dissonance Reduction." Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 47:738-748. Cooper, J. 1998. "Unwanted Consequences and the Self: In Search of the Motivation for Dissonance Reduction." In Cognitive Dissonance Theory: Revival with Revisions and Controversies, ed. E. Harmon-Jones and J. S. Mills. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Cross, S. E., and L. Madson. 1997. "Models of the Self: Self-Construals and Gender." Psychological Bulletin 122:5-37. Davis, Madeline, and David Wallbridge. 1981. Boundary and Space: An Introduction to the Work of D. W. Winnicott. New York: Brunner/Mazel. DeWaal, Frans. 1996. Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Dunning, D., and Hayes, A. F. 1996. "Evidence of Egocentric Comparison in Social Judgment." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 71:213-229. Elster, J. 1986. The Multiple Self. New York: Cambridge University Press. Erikson, E. 1959. Childhood and Society. 1st ed. New York: Norton. Festinger, L. 1957. A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Festinger, L., and Aronson, E. 1960. "The Arousal and Reduction of Dissonance in Social Contexts." In Group Dynamics, ed. D. Cartwright and A. Zander. Evanston: Row, Peterson. Festinger, L., H. W. Riecken, and S. Schachter. 1956. When Prophesy Fails. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Fiske, S. T., and S. E. Taylor. 1991. Social Cognition. 2nd ed. New York: McGraw-Hill. Foot, P. 1978. Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. Berkeley: University of California Press. Gallup, G. G. 1977. "Self-Recognition in Primates: A Comparative Approach to the Bi-directional Properties of Consciousness." American Psychologist 32:329-339. Gallup, G. G. 1993. "Mirror, Mirror on the Wall, Which is the Most Heuristic Theory of Them All." New Ideas in Psychology 11:37-335. Gallup, G. G., and S. D. Suarez. 1986. "Self-Awareness and the Emergency of Mind in Humans and Other Primates." In Psychological Perspectives on the Self, ed. J. Suls and A. G. Greenwald. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. Gerard, H. B., and G. C. Mathewson. 1966. "The Effects of Severity of Initiation on Liking for a Group: A Replication." Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 2:278-287. Gewirth, A. 1998. Self-Fulfillment. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Gies, M. 1987. Anne Frank Remembered. New York: Simon and Schuster. Gilligan, Carol, Nona Lyons, and Trudy Hammer, ed. 1990. Making Connections: The Relational Worlds of Adolescent Girls at the Emma Willard School Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Gilovich, T., V. H. Medvec, and S. Chen. 1995. "Commission, Omission, and Dissonance Reduction: Coping with Regret in the 'Monty Hall' Problem." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 21:182-190. Glass, James. 1997. Life Unworthy of Life: Racial Phobia and Mass Murder in Hitler's Germany. New York: Basic Books. Graziano, W. G., L. A. Jensen-Campbell, and J. E Finch. 1997. "The Self as a Mediator between Personality and Adjustment." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 73:392-404. Gross, M. 1997. Ethics and Activism: The Theory and Practice of Political Morality. New York: Cambridge University Press. Habermas, J. 1984-1987. The Theory of Communicative Action. Translated by Thomas McCarthy. Boston: Beacon Press. Harmon-Jones, E., and J. S. Mills. 1998. Cognitive Dissonance Theory: Revival with Revisions and Controversies. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Harris, Zellig. 1960. Structural Linguistics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Harris, Zellig. 1970. Transformational Linguistics. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel. Hart, D., and W. Damon. 1986. "Developmental Trends in Self-Understanding." Social Cognition 4:388-407. Higgins, E. T. 1987. "Self-Discrepancy: A Theory Relating Self and Affect." Psychological Review 94:319-340. Higgins, E. T. 1996. "The 'Self-Digest': Self-Knowledge Serving Self-Regulatory Functions." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 71:1062-1083. Kant, Immanuel. 1785. The Metaphysics of Morality. Lewis Beck White, Translator. Kekes, John. 1989. Facing Evil. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Kekes, John. 1995. Moral Wisdom and Good Lives. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Keneally, T. 1982. Schindler's List. New York: Simon and Schuster. Kihlstrom, J. F., and S. B. Klein. 1994. "The Self as a Knowledge Structure." In Handbook of Social Cognition. Vol. 1, ed. R. S. Wyer and T. K. Scrull. Basic Processes. Kohut, Heinz. 1971. The Analysis of the Self: A Systematic Approach to the Psychoanalytic Treatment of Narcissistic Personality Disorders. New York: International Universities Press. Kohut, Heinz. 1973. The Restoration of the Self. New York: International Universities Press. Kohut, Heinz. 1985. Self Psychology and the Humanities: Reflections on a New Psychoanalytic Approach. ed. Charles Strozier. New York: Norton. Kripke, Saul. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition. Oxford: Blackwell Kupperman, J. 1991. Character. New York: Oxford University Press. Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1999. Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and its Challenge to Western Thought. New York: Basic Books. Lerner, Richard M. 1992. Final Solutions: Biology, Prejudice, and Genocide. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Lewis, M. 1986. "Origins of Self-Knowledge and Individual Differences in Early Self-Recognition." In Psychological Perspectives on the Self. Vol. 3. ed. J. Suls and A. G. Greenwald. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. Livesley, W. J., and D. B. Bromley. 1973. Person Perception in Childhood and Adolescence. New York: Wiley. MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981/1984. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. London: Duckworth. Markus, H.R., and P. Nurius. 1986. "Possible Selves." American Psychologist 41:954-969. Markus, H.R.J. Smith, and L. Moreland. 1985. "Role of the Self-Concept in the Social Perceptions of Others." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 49:1494-1512. Mellema, G. 1991.Beyond the Call of Duty: Supererogation, Obligation and Offence. Albany: State University of New York Press. Mischel, W., N. Cantor, and S. Feldman. 1996. "Principles of Self-Regulation: The Nature of Willpower and Self-Control." In Social Psychology: Handbook of Basic Principles, ed. E. T. Higgins and A. W. Kruginski. New York: Guilford. Monroe, K. R. 1990. "Altruism and the Theory of Rational Action: An Analysis of Rescuers of Jews in Nazi-Europe." Ethics 101:103-122. Expanded version printed in The Economic Approach to Politics. K. R. Monroe (ed.). New York: HarperCollins, 1991. Monroe, K. R. 1991. "John Donne's People: Explaining Differences between Rational Actors and Altruists through Cognitive Frameworks." The Journal of Politics 53:394-433. Monroe, K. R. 1994. "'But What Else Could I Do' A Cognitive Theory of Ethical Political Behavior." Political Psychology 15:201-226. Monroe, K. R. 1995. "The Psychology of Genocide: A Review of the Literature." Ethics and International Affairs 9:215-239. Monroe, K. R. 1996. The Heart of Altruism: Perceptions of a Common Humanity. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Monroe, K. R. 2001. A Different Way of Seeing Things: Moral Choice During the Holocaust. Book Manuscript. Monroe, K. R., James Hankin, and Renee VanVechten. "The Psychological Foundations of Identity Politics." Palo Alto, Annual Reviews. Annual Review of Political Science 3:419-447. Montemayor, R., and M. Eisen. 1977. "The Development of Self-Conceptions from Childhood to Adolescence." Developmental Psychology 13:314-319. Noddings, Nell. 1999. "Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics." In The Good Life, ed. Charles Guignon. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Nussbaum, M. 1986. The Fragility of Goodness. New York: Cambridge University Press. Oliner, S. and Oliner, P. 1988. The Altruistic Personality. New York: The Free Press. Patterson, M., and K. R. Monroe. 1998. "Narrative" The Annual Review of Political Science. Palo Alto: The Annual Reviews. Pelham, B. W. 1991. "On Confidence and Consequence: The Certainty and Importance of Self-Knowledge.'" Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 60:518-530. Phybus, E. 1982. "Saints and Heroes." Philosophy 57:193-200. Povinelli, D. J. 1993. "Reconstructing the Evolution of Mind." American Psychologist 48:493-509. Povinelli, D. J. 1994. "A Theory of Mind is in the Head, Not the Heart" Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17:573-574. Povinelli, D. J., K. R. Landau, and H. K. Perilloux. 1996. "Self-Recognition in Young Children Using Delayed versus Live Feedback: Evidence of a Developmental Asynchrony." Child Development 67:1540-1554. Rittener, C., and S. Myers. 1986. The Courage to Care. Film and book published by New York: New York University Press. Rosenberg, M.J. 1979. Conceiving the Self. New York: Basic Books. Sedikides, C., and J. J. Skowronski. 1997. "The Symbolic Self in Evolutionary Context." Personality and Social Psychology Review 1 80-102. Slote, M. 1983. Goods and Virtues. New York: Oxford University Press. Smiley, Marion. 1992. Moral Responsibility and the Boundaries of Community: Power and Accountability from a Pragmatic Point of View. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Smith, Adam. 1966. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. New York: A. M. Kelly. Statman, D. 1997. Virtue Ethics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Staub, Ervin. 1989. The Roots of Evil: The Origins of Genocide and Other Group Violence. New York: Cambridge University Press. Symons, C. S., and B. T. Johnson. 1997. "The Self-Reference Effect in Memory." Psychological Bulletin 121:371-394. Tajfel, Henri. 1970. "Experiments in Intergroup Discrimination." Scientific American. 223:96-102. Taylor, Richard. 1985. Ethics, Faith and Reason. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall. Tec, N. 1986. When Light Pierced the Darkness. New York: Oxford University Press. Tetlock, P. 1981. "The Influence of Self-Presentational Goals on Attributional Reports." Social Psychology Quarterly 44:300-311. Thibodeau, R., and E. Aronson. 1992. "Taking a Closer Look: Reasserting the Role of the Self-Concept in Dissonance Theory." Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 18:591-602. Toulmin, S. 1958. An Examination of the Place of Reason in Ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press. Turner, John C., and M. A. Hogg. 1987. Rediscovering the Social Group: A Self-Categorization Theory. Oxford and New York: Basil Blackwell. Wicklund, R., and J. Brehm. 1998. "Resistance to Change: The Cornerstone of Cognitive Dissonance Theory." In Cognitive Dissonance Theory: Revival with Revisions and Controversies, ed. E. Harmon-Jones and J.S. Mills. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. Williams, 1981. Moral Luck. New York: Cambridge University Press. Winnicott, Donald W. 1986. Home Is Where We Start From. New York: Penguin. Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(“Kantian Moral Theory Book Report/Review Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 5000 words”, n.d.)
Kantian Moral Theory Book Report/Review Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 5000 words. Retrieved from https://studentshare.org/philosophy/1532518-kantian-moral-theory
(Kantian Moral Theory Book Report/Review Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 5000 Words)
Kantian Moral Theory Book Report/Review Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 5000 Words. https://studentshare.org/philosophy/1532518-kantian-moral-theory.
“Kantian Moral Theory Book Report/Review Example | Topics and Well Written Essays - 5000 Words”, n.d. https://studentshare.org/philosophy/1532518-kantian-moral-theory.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF Kantian Ethics: A Comparative Analysis of Kant's Moral Theory

Kantian Sincerity and Professional Ethics

Professional Ethics kantian ethics describe that those acts should be considered as right which seek our good will.... hellip; Sincerity can be understood as a moral standard arising from within a person, and is based on truth of word and action.... Palmquist writes in his book that Kantian's good will considers acts to be virtuous, good, and sincere, by associating them with the moral law coming from within the person, rather than weighing the acts on some external principle, lying outside the person....
4 Pages (1000 words) Assignment

Shortcomings With Kantian Ethics

Agitated from emotion, she said that she had contemplated suicide but because of kant's theory, she had decided otherwise (Langton, 1992:2).... This paper ''kantian ethics'' tells that Immanuel Kant came up with an ethical theory that was duty-oriented, which required people to first determine their duty to do what is considered ethical.... This was kantian ethics and it required individuals to act according to their duties, which were of moral law....
10 Pages (2500 words) Essay

Kant's ethical theory

n the realm of any ethical theory,there are some standpoints that can be taken,so an ethical system could be Deontological,Teleological,Consequentialist,Relativism/Subjectivism,and Virtue Based Theories.... His findings provide a wide spectrum of implications in order to establish the frameworks of Absolute Empiricism,Absolute Rationalism and Absolute Idealism In the realm of any ethical theory, there are some standpoints that can be taken, so an ethical system could be Deontological, Teleological, Consequentialist, Relativism/Subjectivism, and Virtue Based Theories....
3 Pages (750 words) Essay

Ethics and Governance

In commercial terms, “Ethical capital reflects the additional revenues created by corporate moral agency, such as a price premium paid by an ethical consumer for an environmentally friendly product”.... hellip; According to the author, on kant's view, what matters in evaluating an action is not the consequence, but the principle that is employed in intending.... Our evaluation of action, on kant's view, will depend on the maxim of the action....
6 Pages (1500 words) Essay

Factors That Determine Peoples Actions

The focus of the paper "Kant's Theory" is on deontological moral theory, the factors that determine people's actions, the law of morality, moral obligations he utilitarians act, developing the maxim, generalizing the statement to conform to natural principles.... This theory promotes human rights.... According to Kant, this theory is so demanding.... He points out that utilitarianism ignores moral obligations and treats them as unnecessary....
6 Pages (1500 words) Assignment

Kantian Moral Ethics

In this essay, I will put into perspective the application of this theory in incidences of violence that entails both self-defense and proactive violence.... ccording to the Kantian theory, morality is not based exclusively on reasoning but also on the moral worth of a given action.... From the paper "Kantian moral Ethics" it is clear that acts of violence are considered moral or immoral on the grounds of whether they promote human dignity, they promote fairness for all parties and that the maxim that is considered moral can be universalized....
6 Pages (1500 words) Essay

Will Theory and the Interest Theory of Rights

This assignment "Will Theory and the Interest Theory of Rights" presents a comparative analysis of the will theory and the interest theory of rights and considers which theory is more plausible.... It is submitted at the outset that the tension between the legal protection of human rights, political constraints, and the extent of individual protection highlights the conflict between legal enforcement of rights in practice and theoretical concepts of ethics based on the will theory (Donnelly, 2003, p....
7 Pages (1750 words) Assignment

Lockes and Kants Moral Theories in the Modern Society

The paper "Locke's and kant's moral Theories in the Modern Society" states that if morality teaches us to follow codes of conduct and to have amenability with accepted individual behavior, then it is only right to let each and every one cooperate with molding something to be morally acceptable.... The comparative analysis in terms of the applications and effects of these theories to all humans in the modern setting is the key point of argumentation.... hellip; The Kantian theory of Immanuel Kant has its own distinct beliefs on the philosophy of morality and its application to humans, but it is not going to be in sync with today's drastically changing world....
5 Pages (1250 words) Essay
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us