They assert that there are engineering ethics that fall under universal standards. They serve to form a basis for the behavior of an engineer even in location or countries where there is no much emphasis on the engineering ethical of formal education on the same (Downey et all, 2007). The “standard” ethical guidelines shape the engineering profession and ensure that the society benefits from the actions of the engineeringfraternity.Nevertheless, the author fails to concentrate on the effects of differentiated inequalities in different countries regardingthe emphasis and implementation of the engineering ethics.
There may be national laws that affect the ethical functioning of the engineer. The Downey et all. (2007) falters in giving the implications of these laws and how to navigate through them. Being an ethical engineer requires not only the control of the engineer’s human behavior through a set of rules and discipline by regulatory frameworks but also personal attributes. Harris (2008) is specific on this issue and attributes virtue ethics as a complimentary essential in themaintenance of professional ethics by engineers.
Accurately, an engineer’s personal discipline, motivation, and commitment to practicing professional ethics is a key determiner of the quality of his practice. This bears a significance to Downey et all (2007) assertions that an engineer be a follower of standard guidelines. Essentially, Harris (2008) prioritizes virtue ethics so as to have the motivation to follow the guidelines that shape the engineering profession. The authors get it spot on by asserting that negative rules do not necessarily guarantee that the engineer will stick to the set rules.
The author notes that the engineering ethics largely concentrates on prevention of the harmful effects of technology and prevention of unethical conduct by the engineers (Harris, 2008). He provides such examples by giving examples of the Colombia and Challenger disasters. True to this, the world continues to see much effort in engineering ethics go in these two ways. The author is correct in stating that negative rules do not cover everything in professional ethics there is more to engineering ethics that preventive measures.
Certainly, the engineer, in his or her path to being an ethical actor requires “aspirational ethics” and virtues that are instructive (Harris, 2008). The author highlights honesty, courage, compassion, and gratitude as some of the virtues that could be instrumental in the engineering profession. The strength of these assertions is clearly manifested and easy to decipher. Certainly, the human perspective, in terms of virtues, is needed in additional to adherence to the moral guidelines set by the engineering ethics bodies.
They serve to increase the ethical performance of an engineer by considering all avenues that make up an ethical engineer. Harris (2008) assertions do not have many weakness about what shapes an engineer as an ethical actor. The only noted weakness is that he does not include ways to cultivate the virtues needed by engineers in different environments. The engineering dynamics are different in many areas as noted by Downey et all (2007). It would have been helpful for the author to include the limitations that affect the upholding on virtues by engineers in different localities as they perform their duties.
Additionally, the article fails to include the ways on how engineers can personally partake and promote the application of virtue ethics in their performance. Individual moral values, alongside adherence to the engineering code of ethics, contribute immensely to the value of the decisions made by engineers. Downey et all (2007) observes that ethical obligations surround engineers in their activities, and the situations demand them to make firm decisions that consider all aspects of the environment and society.
Lynchand Kline (2000) focuses on the individual morality of decision making as a guideline to shaping engineer who is also an ethical actor.
Read More